/O ./Icucevrlc Thornton &S», Booksellers, II The Rroai "/i'kt g^^^ UCSB LIBRARY ARISTOTLE'S POLITICS TRANSLATED BY BENJAMIN JOWETT WITH INTRODUCTION, ANALYSIS AND INDEX BV H. W. C. DAVIS, M.A. FELLOW OF BALLIOU OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1916 OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS LONDON EDINBURGH GLASGOW NEW YORK TORONTO MELBOURNE BOMBAY HUMPHREY MILFORD PUBLISHER TO THE UNIVEKSITY CONTENTS Introduction Analysis . The Politics. Book I . II III IV V VI VII VIII Index PAGE I 25 54 100 145 187 237 257 300 319 Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2008 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/aristotlespolitiOOaris INTRODUCTION The life of Aristotle, so far as it Illustrates this treatise, may be summarized in a few words. He was by birth a Greek, but a native of the small city of Stageira which stood upon the fringe of the Greek world ; he was therefore well fitted by his origin to be an impartial, yet sympathetic critic, of the more famous city-states of Greece. In his youth he studied philosophy at Athens under Plato, thus coming at the most impressionable period of his life into close relations with the profoundest thinker whom Greece had yet produced. After the death of Plato (347), he quitted Athens to spend some years in the service of the new race of monarchs whose mission it was to diffiise Greek culture through the East and at the same time to complete the destruction of all that was most valuable and characteristic in the political life of Greece. At the court of Hermias, the obscure tyrant of the obscure city of Atarneus, Aristotle had the opportunity of observing the once great, but then decadent, despotism of Persia, to which he makes some references in the Politics. In 343 or 342 he migrated to Macedonia, joined the court of Philip, and acted for three years or so as tutor to the youthful Alexander. The results of his experience in Macedonia, and the drift of the political teaching which he gave to his pupil may perhaps be inferred from the comments which, in several passages of the Politics, he passes on monarchies and tyrannies. About the year 335, on the eve of Alex- ander's great campaigns of conquest, the philosopher turned his back on Macedonia ; we may infer from what he says of empires, that while he realized their possible services to civili- OAVI3 R 2 Introduction zation, he was still more alive to the dangers, moral and other, which beset the path of a military and aggressive state. His sympathies were with the past, not the future ; with Sparta and Athens rather than with Macedon ; with Plato rather than with Alexander. Settling down at Athens, he became the leader of a philosophic school, the director of a brilliant academy ; but he incurred the odium to which a friend of Macedon was naturally exposed in the city of Demosthenes. In 323, after the death of his pupil and patron, he was driven into exile by a prosecution for impiety which, if he had faced it, would probably have brought upon his head the fate of Socrates. He died in the following year at Chalcis, a Macedonian stronghold. The semi-barbarians, of whose future he doubted, had been more generous to him than the Greeks, whose highest thought it had been his life-work to interpret and to vindicate. Of his literary work in general this is not the place to speak. It is enough to say that he aimed at expounding in the light of his own philosophic principles all the sciences which were then recognized, and that he followed consis- tently the method, of which the Politics are a conspicuous illustration, of combining induction with deductive reasoning from first principles, and of testing his own conclusions by a comparison with popular opinions and those of other teachers. Encyclopaedic knowledge has never, before or since, gone hand in hand with a logic so masculine or with speculation so profound. But it is in dealing with the moral rather than the natural sciences that he is greatest, most ade- quately equipped with facts, and most interested in his subject. Of his work in the moral sciences the final results are incorporated in the Nicomachean Ethics and the Politics. The two treatises are intimately connected. In the Ethics he Introduction 3 discusses the nature of individual happiness or well-being ; in the Politics he treats of the state as one of the chief means through which the individual attains to happiness. The object of the Poiii'ics is both practical and speculative ; to explain the nature of the ideal city in which the end of happi- ness may be completely realized ; to suggest some methods of making existent states more useful to the individual citizen than they were in Aristotle's time, or had been in the past. Aristotle is not, strictly speaking, the founder of political science. In the age of Pericles, and earlier still, statesmen and philosophers had theorized about the origin of society, the relative merits of various constitutions, and other kindred topics. Though Socrates was more concerned U'ith ethics than with politics, he applied the powerful solvent of his dialectic to many of the political ideas which were fashionable in his day. The conceptions of utility as the ideal which the statesman should pursue, and of scientific knowledge as the indispensable equipment of the statesman, would seem to have had their birth in the Socratic circle. Plato, the pupil of Socrates, not content with developing the suggestions of his master and with giving to the Socratic formulae a deeper meaning, essayed a more systematic discussion of the nature of the state and its right organization. In the Republic he describes the state as it would appear if founded and governed by philosophers ; in the Laws he offered to the statesmen of his age a model more practicable and more nearly related to the experience of the past ; a model which the legislator for a new colony might follow without undue violence to Greek prejudices and opinions. Although the views of Plato aie sharply, and not always justly, criticized by Aristotle, the influence of the Republic and the Latus is perceptible in many places of the Politics where they are not mentioned. B 2 4 Introduction The Politics, in fiict, would not be so valuable as they are if they expressed the views of an individual man of genius and nothing more. Here as elsewhere it is not the least of Aristotle's merits that he epitomized the best thoughts of a nation and of a stage in human history. He respected the political thinkers of the past, both the statesmen and the theorists ; he was loth to admit that any institution or polity which had stood the test of time could be altogether bad. Hence he appears before us as a mediator in the controversies of his own and the preceding ages. It is his wish to lay bare the grain of truth which exists at the core of every political practice and belief. He interprets even those ideals with which he is least in sympathy. And so we learn from him what the various types of the city-state signified to the Greek mind ; we are admitted under his guidance to the penetralia of their political thought. The history of the Greek city-state we can study for our- selves, with fewer sources of information, it is true, than Aristotle had at his command, but also with a more critical appreciation of their value and a more scientific method of interpretation than was to be learned in Athenian schools of the fourth century. We are too in a better position than Aristotle to see the true place of the city-state in the evolution of society, to appreciate its limitations, to condemn its evils, and to draw the moral from its failure. We know, what he does not appear to have suspected, that the careers of his ( Macedonian patrons had sealed the death-warrant of the community which he regarded as the highest that human skill was capable of framing. Ampler experience has shown us that slavery is not the indispensable basis of a civilization, nor commerce always degrading to the individual and destruc- tive of national morality. In the modern world we have Introduction y before us communities which, in defiance of his prophecies, have become extensive without becoming disunited. By his own methods of induction and comparison we can refute some of the laws which he regarded as immutable. Still we must start from Aristotle. His account of the city-state may be supplemented and corrected, but not super- seded. The governing ideas of any polity are always best expressed by those to whom they stand for the absolute and final ti-uth ; and there is no form of polity which the student of political science should study with more care than the city-state. Just because it is comparatively simple, just because it is unlike the states with which we are personally acquainted, it contains the key to many modern problems. Aristotle is the best inter- preter of an essential link in the chain of political development. But he is something more than this, more than a Greek who states the case of Greece. He is also a philosopher and a student of human nature. His views as to the origin and ultimate structure of society, as to the aims of civic life, as to the mutual obligations of the state and the individual, as to the nature of political justice, all have a value which is independent of his historical position. It is often difficult to follow his discussions of these and cognate subjects. His arguments are stated with extreme conciseness, and the train of thought which leads him from one topic to another is often far from clear. But those who have the patience to wrestle with his text will find in it theories of perennial value, and refutations of fallacies which are always re-emerging. Nor is it merely from his more abstract disquisitions that such lessons are to be extracted. While there could be no greater mistake than to apply his criticisms of democracies and aristocracies to modern governments which go by the same names, without stopping to enquire how far the names have changed their 6 Introduction meanings, it is on the other hand often apparent that these criticisms, when the necessary qualifications have been made, are as time of the present as they were of Greece. Of this an illustration may be found in the account of revolutions and their causes which foi ms the fifth book of the Politics. The Politics should probably be regarded as an unfinished work. There are not infrequent repetitions ; some subjects which the author promises to treat are never treated ; and we are sometimes at a loss for the connecting link betweien suc- cessive books or parts of the same book. The traditional order of the books is probably not that which Aristotle con- templated, and has been altered by most editors. The pre- sent translation follows the order of Bekker's first edition ; the numbering of the books in his octavo edition of 1878 has been given in brackets wherever it differs from that of the first. None of the rearrangements which have been sug- gested are completely satisfactory. Whichever of them is adopted, the reader will find that positions assumed at an earlier are only proved at a later stage of the argument. The Politics should be treated as a quarry of arguments and theories rather than as an artistically constructed piece of literature. It is best studied by the collection and com- parison of all the passages which bear upon the same topic. It is hoped that for this purpose the subject-headings in the Index, which is abridged from that of the translator, may be of service. A brief analysis is prefixed to the translation with the object of explaining the thread of the argument, where such a thread exists, of indicating the natural divisions of the text, and of enumerating the chief topics of discussion. The thanks of the editor are due to tlie Master of Balliol for his kindness in revising the proof of this Introduction. H. W. C. DAVIS. BOOK I. cc. I, 2. Definition and structure of the State. The state is the highest form of community and aims at the highest good. How it differs from other communities will appear if we examine the parts of which it is composed (c. i). It consists of villages which consist of households. The household is founded upon the two relations of male and female, of master and slave ; it exists to satisfy man's daily needs. The village, a wider community, satisfies a wider range of needs. The state aims at satisfying all the needs of men. Men form states to secure a bare subsistence ; but the ultimate object of the state is the good life. The naturalness of the state is proved by the faculty of speech in man. In the order of Nature the state precedes the household and th-e individual. It is founded on a natural impulse, that towards political association (c. 2). cc. 3-13. Household economy. The Slave. Property. Children and Wives. Let us discuss the household, since the state is composed of households (c. 3). First as to slavery. The slave is a piece of property which is animate, and useful for action rather than for production (c. 4). Slavery is natural ; in every department of the natural universe we find the relation of ruler and subject. There are human beings who, without possessing reason, understand it. These are natural slaves (c. 5). But we find persons in slavery who are not natural slaves. Hence slavery itself is condemned by some ; but they are wrong. The natural slave benefits by subjection to a master (c. 6). The art of ruling slaves ditfers from that of 8 Analysis ruling free men but calls for no detailed description ; any one who is a natural master can acquire it for himself (c. 7). As to property and the modes of acquiring it. This subject concerns us in so far as property is an indispensable substratum to the household (c. 8), But we do not need that form of finance which accumulates wealth for its own sake. This is unnatural finance. It has been made possible by the invention of coined money. It accumulates money by means of exchange. Natural and unnatural finance are often treated as though they were the same, but differ in their aims (c. 9) ; also in their subject matter ; for natural finance is only concerned with the fruits of the earth and animals (c. 10). Natural finance is necessaiy to the householder; he must therefore know about live stock, agriculture, possibly about the exchange of the products of the earth, such as wood and minerals, for money. Special treatises on finance exist, and the subject should be specially studied by statesmen (c. II). Lastly, we must discuss and distinguish the relations of husband to wife, of father to child (c. 12). In household management persons call for more attention than things ; free persons for more than slaves. Slaves are only capable of an inferior kind of virtue. Socrates vs^as wrong in denying that there are several kinds of virtue. Still the slave must be trained in virtue. The education of the free man will be subsequently discussed (c. 13). BOOK II. cc. 1-8. Ideal Commonivealths— Plato, Phaleas, Hippodamus. To ascertain the nature of the ideal state we should start by examining both the best states of history and the best that Analysis 9 theorists have imagined. Otlierwise we might waste our time over problems which otheis have ah-eady solved. Among theorists, Plato in the Republic raises the most fundamental questions. He desires to abolish private pi'operty and the family (c. i). But the end which he has in view is wrong. He wishes to make all his citizens absolutely alike ; but the differentiation of functions is a law of nature. There can be too much unity in a state (c. 2). And the means by which he would promote unity are wrong. The abolition of property will produce, not remove, dissension. Communism of wives and children will destroy natural affection (c. 3). Other objections can be raised ; but this is the fatal one (c. 4). To descend to details. The advantages to be expected from communism of property would be better secured if private property were used in a liberal spirit to relieve the wants of others. Private property makes men happier, and enables them to cultivate such virtues as ■ generosity. The Republic makes unity the result of uni- formity among the citizens, which is not the case. The good sense of mankind has always been against Plato, and experiment would show that his idea is impracticable (c. 5). Plato sketched another ideal state in the Laws ; it was meant to be more practicable than the other. In the Laius he abandoned communism, but otherwise upheld the leading ideas of the earlier treatise, except that he made the new state larger and too large. He forgot to discuss foreign relations, and to fix a limit of private property, and to restrict the increase of population, and to distin<^ish between ruler and subject. The form of government which he proposed was bad (c. 6). ro Analysis Phaleas of Chalcedon made equal distribution of property the main feature of his scheme. This would be difficult to effect, and would not meet the evils which Phaleas had in mind. Dissensions arise from deeper causes than inequality of wealth. His state would be weak against foreign foes. His reforms would anger the rich and not satisfy the poor (c. 7). Hippodamus, who was not a practical politician, aimed at symmetry. In his state there were to be three classes, three kinds of landed property, three sorts of laws. He also proposed to (i) create a Court of Appeal, (2) let juries qualify their verdicts, (3) reward those who made discoveries of public utility. His classes and his property system were badly devised. Qualified verdicts are impossible since jurymen may not confer together. The law about discoveries would encourage men to tamper with the Constitution. Now laws when obsolete and absurd should be changed ; but needless changes diminish the respect for law (c. 8). cc. 9—12. The best existent states — Sparta^ Crete, and Carthage — Greek laivgluers. The Spartans cannot manags tiieir serf population. Their women are too influential and too luxurious. Their property system has concentrated all wealth in a few hands. Hence the citizen body has decreased. There are points to criticize in the Ephorate, the Senate, the Kingship, the common meals, the Admiralty. The Spartan and his state are only fit for war. Yet even in war Sparta is hampered by the want of a financial system (c. 9). The Cretan cities resemble Sj)arta in their constitutions, but are more primitive. Their common meals are better Analy. sis I I managed. But the Cosmi are worse than the Ephors. The Cretan constitution is a narrow and factious oligarchy ; the cities are saved from destruction osly by their inaccessibility (c. lo). The Carthaginian polity is highly praised, and not without reason. It may be compared with the Spartan ; it is an oligarchy with some democratic features. It lays stress upon wealth ; in Carthage all offices are bought and sold. Also, one man may hold several offices together. These are bad features. But the discontent of the peoj^le is soothed by schemes of emigration (c. ii). Of lawgivers, Solon was the best ; conservative when possible, and a moderate democrat. About Philolaus, Cha- rondas, Phaleas, Draco, Pittacus, and Androdamas there is little to be said (c. 12). BOOK III. cc. 1-5- The Cidzen, civic virtue, and the civic body. How are we to define a citizen ? He is more than a mere denizen; private rights do not make a citizen. He is ordi- narily one who possesses political power ; who sits on juries and in the assembly. But it is hard to find a definition which applies to all so-called citizens. To define him as the son of citizen parents is futile (c. i). Some say that his civic rights must have been justly acquired. But he is a citizen who has political power, however acquired (c. 2). Similarly the state is defined by reference to the distribution of political power ; when the mode of distribution is changed a new state comes into existence (c. 3). The good citizen may not be a good man ; the good citizen is one who does good service to his state, and this state may 1 2 Analysis be bad in principle. In a constitutional state the good citizen "knows both how to rule and how to obey. The good man is one who is fitted to rule. But the citizen in a constitu- I tional state learns to rule by obeying orders. Therefore citizen- \ ship in such a state is a moral training (c. 4). Mechanics will not be citizens in the best state. Extreme democracies, and some oligarchies, neglect this rule. But cir- cumstances oblige them to do this. They have no choice (c. 5). cc. 6—13. The Classification of Constitutions ; Democracy and Oligarchy ; Kingship. . The aims of the state are two ; to satisfy man's social \ instinct, and to fit him for the good life. Political rule differs from that over slaves in aiming primarily at the good of those who are ruled (c. 6). Constitutions are bad or good according as the common welfare is, or is not, their aim. Of good Constitutions there are three : Monarchy, Aris- tocracy, and Polity. Of bad there are also three : Tyranny, Oligarchy, Extreme Democracy. The bad are perversions of the good (c. 7). Democracies and Oligarchies are not made by the numeri- cal proportion of the rulers to the ruled. Democracy is the rule of the poor; oligarchy is that of the rich (c. 8). Democrats take Equality for their motto ; oligarchs believe that political rights should be unequal and proportionate to wealth. But both sides miss the true object of the state, which is virtue. Those who do most to promote virtue deserve the gi-eatest share of power (c. 9). On the same principle, Justice is not the will of the majority or of the wealthier, but that course of action which the moral aim of Analysis 1 3 the state requires (c. lo). But are the Many or the Few likely to be the better rulers ? It would be unreasonable to give the highest offices to the Many. But they have a faculty of criticism which fits them for deliberative and judicial power. The good critic need not be an expert ; experts are sometimes bad judges. Moreover, the Many have a greater stake in the city than the Few. But the governing body, whether Few or Many, must be held in check by the laws (c. 11). On what principle should political power be distributed ? Granted that equals deserve equal shares ; who are these equals ? Obviously those who are equally able to be of service to the state (c. 12). Hence there is something in the claims advanced by the wealthy, the free born, the noble, the highly gifted. But no one of these classes should be allowed to rule the rest. A state should consist of men who are equal, or nearly so, in wealth, in birth, in moral and intellectual excellence. The principle which underlies Ostra- 1 cism is plausible. But in the ideal state, if a pre-eminent individual be found, he should be made a king (c. 1 3). cc. 14-18. The Forms of Monarchy. Of Monarchy there are five kinds, (i) the Spartan, (2) the Barbarian, (3) the elective dictatorship, (4) the Heroic, (5) Absolute Kingship (c. 14). The last of these forms might appear the best polity to some ; that is, if the king acts as the embodiment of law. For he will dispense from the law in the spirit of the law. But this power would be less abused if reserved for the Many. Monarchy arose to meet the needs of primitive society ; it is now obsolete and on various grounds objectionable (c. 15). It tends to become hereditary; it subjects equals to the rule of an equal. The individual 1 4 Analysis monarch may be misled by his passions, and no single man can attend to all the duties of government (c. i6). One case alone can be imagined in which Absolute Kingship would be just (c. 17). Let us consider the origin and nature of the best polity, now that we have agreed not to call Absolute Kingship the best (c. 18). BOOK IV (VI). cc. i-io. Variations of the main types oj" Constitutions. Political science should study (i) the ideal state, (2) those states which may be the best obtainable under special circum- stances, and even (3) those which are essentially bad. For the statesman must sometimes make the best of a bad Con- stitution (c. i). Of our six main types of state, Kingship and Aristocracy have been discussed (cf. Bk: III, c. 14 fol.). Let us begin by dealing with the other four and their divisions, enquiring also when and why they may be desirable (c. 2). First as to Democracy and Oligarchy. The common view that Democracy and Oligarchy should be taken as the main types of Constitution is at variance with our own view and wrong (c. 3). So is the view that the numerical propor- tion of rulers to ruled makes the difference between these two types ; in a Democracy the Many are also the poor, in an Oligarchy the Few are also the wealthy. In every state the distinction between rich and poor is the most funda- mental of class-divisions. Still Oligarchy and Democracy are important types ; and their variations arise from differences in the character of the ricfi and the poor by whom they are ruled. Of Democracies there are four kinds. The worst, ex- Ana ly- sis ly treme Democi'acy, is that in which all offices are open to all, and the will of the people overrides all law (c. 4). Of Oligarchies too there are four kinds ; the worst is that in which offices are hereditary and the magistrates uncontrolled by law (c. 5). These variations arise under circumstances which may be briefly described (c. 6). Of Aristocracy in the strict sense there is but one form, that in which the best men alone are citizens (c. 7). Polity is a compromise between Democracy and Oligarchy, but inclines to the Democratic side. Many so-called Aris- tocracies are really Polities (c. 8). There are different ways of efrecting the compromise which makes a Polity. The Laconian Constitution is an example of a successful com- promise (c. 9). Tyranny is of three kinds: (i) the barbarian despotism, and (2) the elective dictatorship have already been discussed ; in both there is rule according to law over willing subjects. But in (3) the strict form of tyranny, there is the lawless rule of one man over unwilling subjects (c. 10). cc. I1-13. Of the Best State both in general and under special circumstances. For the average city-state the best constitution will be a mean between the rule of rich and poor ; the middle-class will be supreme. No state will be well administered unless the middle-class holds sway. The middle-class is stronger in large than in small states. Hence in Greece it has rarely attained to power ; especially as democracy and oligarchy were aided by the influence of the leading states (c. 11). No constitution can dispense with the support of the strongest class in the state. Hence Democracy and Oligarchy are the 1 6 Analysis only constitutions possible in some states. But in these cases the legislator should conciliate the middle-class (c. 12). Whatever form of constitution be adopted there are expedients to be noted which may help in preserving it (c. 1 3). cc. 14—16. Ho'U) to proceed in framing a Constitution. The legislator must pay attention to three subjects in par- ticular ; {a) The Deliberative Assembly which is different in each form of constitution (c. 14). {h) The Executive. Here he must know what offices are indispensable and which of them may be conveniently combined in the person of one magistrate ; also whether the same offices should be supreme in every state ; also which of the twelve or more methods of making appointments should be adopted in each case (c. 1 5). (c) The Courts of Law. Here he must consider the kinds of law-courts, their spheres of action, their methods of procedure (c. 16), BOOK V (VIII). cc. 1—4. Of Revolutions, and their causes in general. Ordinary states are founded on erroneous ideas of justice, which lead to discontent and revolution. Of revolutions some are made to introduce a new Constitution, others to modify the old, others to put the working of the Constitution in new hands. Both Democracy and Oligarchy contain inherent flaws which lead to revolution, but Democracy is the more stable of the two types (c. i). We may distinguish between the frame of mind which fosters revolution, the objects for which it is started, and the provocative causes (c. 2). The latter deserve a more detailed account (c. 3). Trifles may be the occasion but are never Analysis 1 7 the true cause of a sedition. One common cause is the aggrandizement of a particular class ; another is a feud be- tween rich and poor when they are evenly balanced and there is no middle-class to mediate. As to the manner of effecting a revolution : it may be carried through by force or fraud (c. 4). cc. 5-12. Revolutions in particular States, and boiv revolutions may be avoided. (a) In Democracies revolutions may arise from a persecu- tion of the rich ; or when a demagogue becomes a general, or when politicians compete for the favour of the mob (c. 5). {b) In Oligarchies the people may rebel against oppression ; ambitious oligarchs may conspire, or appeal to the people, or set up a tyrant. Oligarchies are seldom destroyed except by the feuds of their own members ; unless they employ a mercenary captain, who may become a tyrant (c. 6). (c) In Aristocracies and Polities the injustice of the ruling class may lead to revolution, but less often in Polities. Aristo- cracies may also be ruined by an unprivileged class, or an ambitious man of talent. Aristocracies tend to become oligarchies. Also they are liable to gradual dissolution; which is true of Polities as well (c. 7). The best precautions against sedition are these : to avoid illegality and frauds upon the unprivileged ; to maintain good feeling between rulers and ruled ; to watch destructive agen- cies ; to alter property qualifications from time to time ; to let no individual or class become too powerful ; not to let magis- tracies be a source of gain ; to beware of class-oppression (c. 8). In all magistrates we should require loyalty, ability, and jus- tice ; we should not carry the principle of the constitution DAVIS C 1 8 Analysis to extremes ; we should educate the citizens in the spirit of a constitution (c. 9). (d^ The causes which destroy and the means which pre- serve a Monarchy must be considered separately. Let us first distinguish between Tyranny and Kingship. Tyranny combines the vices of Democracy and Oligarchy. Kingship is exposed to the same defects as Aristocracy. But both these kinds of Monarchy are especially endangered by the insolence of their representatives and by the fear or contempt which they inspire in others. Tyranny is weak against both external and domestic foes ; Kingship is strong against inva- sion, weak against sedition (c. 10). Moderation is the best preservative of Kingship. Tyranny may rely on the traditional expedients of demoralizing and dividing its subjects, or it may imitate Kingship by showing moderation in expenditure, and courtesy and temperance in social relations, by the wise use of ministers, by holding the balance evenly between the rich and poor (c. 11). But the Tyrannies of the past have been short-lived. Plato's discussion of revolutions in the Republic is inade- quate ; e. g. he does not explain the results of a revolution against a tyranny, and could not do so on his theory ; nor is he correct about the cause of revolution in an Oligarchy ; nor does he distinguish between the different varieties of Oligarchy and Democracy (c. 12). BOOK VI (VII). cc. 1-8. Concerning the proper organization of Democracies and Oligarchies. (A) Democracies differ infer se (i) according to the character of the citizen body, (2) according to the mode in which the Analy sis 19 characteristic features of democracy are combined (c. i). Liberty is the first principle of democracy. The results of liberty are that the numerical majority is supreme, and that each man lives as he likes. From these characteristics we may easily infer the other features of democracy (c. 2). In oligarchies it is not the numerical majority, but the wealthier men, who are supreme. Both these principles are unjust if the supreme authority is to be absolute and above the law. Both numbers and wealth should have their share of influence. But it is hard to find the true principles of political justice, and harder still to make men act upon them (c. 3). Democracy has four species (cf. Bk. IV, c. 4). The best is (i) an Agricultural Democracy, in which the magistrates are elected by, and responsible to, the citizen body, while each office has a property qualification proportionate to its importance. These democracies should encourage agriculture by legislation. The next best is (2) the Pastoral Democracy. Next comes (3) the Commercial Democracy. Worst of all is (4) the Extreme Democracy with manhood suffrage (c. 4). It is harder to preserve than to found a Democracy. To preserve it we must prevent the j oor from plundering the rich ; we must not exhaust the public revenues by giving pay for the performance of public duties; we must prevent the growth of a pauper class (c. 5). (B) The modes of founding Oligarchies call for little ex- planation. Careful organization is the best way of preserving these governments (c. 6). Much depends on the military aiTangements ; oligarchs must not make their subjects too powerful an element in the army. Admission to the governing body should be granted on easy conditions. Office should be made a burden, not a source of profit (c. 7). c 2 2 o Analysis Both in oligarchies and democracies the right arrangement of offices is important. Some kinds of office are necessary in every state; others are peculiai- to special types of state (c. 8). BOOK Vn (IV). CO. r-3. The Summum Bonumfor ind'ivicluah and states. Before constructing the ideal state we must know what is the most desirable life for states and individuals. True happiness flows from the possession of wisdom and virtue, and not from the possession of external goods. But a virtuous life must be equipped with external goods as instruments. These laws hold good of both states and individuals (c. i). But does the highest virtue consist in contemplation or in action ? The states of the past have lived for action in the shape of war and conquest. But war cannot be regarded as a reasonable object for a state (c. 2). A virtuous life implies activity, but activity may be speculative as well as practical. Those are wrong who regard the life of a practical politician as degrading. But again they are wrong who treat political power as the highest good (c. 3). cc. 4-12. A picture of the Ideal State. We must begin by considering the population and the territory. The former should be as small as we can make it without sacrificing independence and the capacity for a moral life. The smaller the population the more manageable it will be (c. 4). The tenitory must be large enough to supply the citizens with the means of living liberally and temperately, with an abundance of leisure. Analysis 2 1 The city should be in a central position (c. 5). Communica- tion with the sea is desirable for economic and military reasons ; but the moral effects of sea-trade are bad. If the state has a marine, the port town should be at some distance from the city (c. 6). The character of the citizens should be a mean between that of Asiatics and that of the northern races ; intelligence and high spirit should be harmoniously blended as they are in some Greek races (c. 7). We must distinguish the members of the state from those who are necessary as its servants, but no part of It. There must be men who are able to provide food, to practise the arts, to bear arms, to carry on the work of exchange, to supervise the state religion, to exercise political and judicial functions (c. 8). But of these classes we should exclude from the citizen body (i) the mechanics, (2) the traders, (3) the husbandmen. Warriors, rulers, priests remain as eligible for citizenship. The same persons should exercise these three professions, but at different periods of life. Ownership of land should be confined to them (c. 9). Such a distinction between a ruling and a subject class, based on a difference of occupation, is nothing new. It still exists in Egypt, and the custom of common meals In Crete and Italy proves that it formerly existed there. Most of the valuable rules of politics have been discovered over and over again in the course of history. In dealing with the land of the state we must distinguish between public demesnes and private estates. Both kinds of land should be tilled by slaves or barbarians of a servile disposition (c. 10). The site of the city should be chosen with regard (i) to public health, (2) to political convenience, (3) to strategic requirements. The ground-plan of the city 2 2 Analysis should be regular enough for beauty, not so regular as to make defensive warfare difficult. Walls are a practical neces- sity (c. 1 1). It is well that the arrangement of the buildings in the city should be carefully thought out (c. 12). cc. 13-17. The Educational System of the Ideal State^ its a'lm^ a?id early stages. The nature and character of the citizens must be determined with reference to the kind of happiness which we desire them to pursue. Happiness was defined in the Ethics as the perfect exercise of virtue, the latter term being understood not in the conditional, but in the absolute sense. Now a man acquires virtue of this kind by the help of nature, habit, and reason (c. 1 3). Habit and reason are the fruits of education, which must therefore be discussed. The citizens should be educated to obey when young and to rule when they are older. Rule is their ultimate and highest function. Since the good ruler is the same as the good man, our education must be so framed as to produce the good man. It should develope all man's powers and fit him for all tlie activities of life ; but the highest powers and the highest activities must be the supreme care of education. An education which is purely military, like the Laconian, neglects this principle (c, 14). The virtues of peace (intellectual culture, temperance, justice) are the most necessary for states and individuals ; war is nothing but a means towards securing peace. But education must follow the natural order of human development, beginning with the body, dealing next with the appetites, and training the intellect last of all (c. 15). To produce a healthy physique the legislator must fix Analysis 23 the age of marriage, regulate the physical condition of the parents, provide for the exposure of infants, and settle the duration of marriage (c. 16). He must also prescribe a physical training for infants and young children. For their moral education the very young should be committed to overseers ; these should select the tales which they are told, their associates, the pictures, plays, and statues which they see. From five to seven years of age should be the period of preparation for intellectual training (c. 17). BOOK VIII (V). CO. 1-7. The Ideal Education continued. Its Music and Gymnastic. Education should be under state-control and the same for all the citizens (c. i). It should comprise those useful studies which every one must master, but none which degrade the mind or body (c. 2). Reading, writing, and drawing have always been taught on the score of their utility ; gymnastic as producing valour. Music is taught as a recreation, but it serves a higher purpose. The noble employment of leisure is the highest aim which a man can pursue ; and music is valuable for this purpose. The same may be said of drawing, and other subjects of education have the same kind of value (c.3). Gymnastic is the first stage of education ; but we must not develope the valour and physique of our children at the expense of the mind, as they do in Sparta. Until puberty, and for three years after, bodily exercise should be light (c. 4). Music, if it were a mere amusement, should not be taught to children ; they would do better by listening 24 Analysis to professionals. But music is a moral discipline and a rational enjoyment (c. 5). By learning music children become better critics and are given a suitable occupation. When of riper age they should abandon music; professional skill is not for them; nor should they be taught difficult instruments (c. 6). The various musical harmonies should be used for different purposes. Some inspire virtue, others valour, others enthusiasm. The ethical harmonies are those which children should learn. The others may be left to professionals. The Dorian harmony is the best for education. The Phrygian is bad ; but the Lydian may be beneficial to children. Cetera desunt. THE POLITICS BOOK I O"^) ■ Every state is a community of some kind, and every •*■• -*■ r Ed. community is established with a view to some good ; for Bekker, mankind always act in order to obtain that which they 1252 a think good. But, if all communities aim at some good, the state or political community, which is the highest of all, I and which embraces all the rest, aims, and in a greater degree than any other, at the highest good. Now there is an erroneous opinion ^ that a statesman, king, 2 householder, and master are the same, and that they differ, not in kind, but only in the number of their subjects. For example, the ruler over a few is called a master ; over more, the manager of a household; over a still larger number, a statesman or king, as if there were no difference between a great household and a small state. The distinction which <^ is made between the king and the statesniaij is as follows:,. \ When the government is personal, the ruler is a king ; when, according to the principles of the political science, the citizens rule and are ruled in turn, then he is called a statesman. ^ But all this is a mistake ; for governments differ in kind, as will be evident to any one who considers the matter according to the method " which has hitherto guided us. As in other departments of science, so in politics, the com- pound should always be resolved into the simple elements or least parts of the whole. We must therefore look at the 1 Cp. Plato, Politicus, 258 e toll. ' Cp. c. 8. § I. f/f'^ 26 Logical Analysis of the State I. 1 elements of which the state is composed, in order that we may see ^ in what they differ from one another, and whether any scientific distinction can be diawn between the different kinds of rule ^. 2 He who thus considers things in their first growth and origin, whether a state or anything else, will obtain the ' 2 clearest view of them. In the first place (f)_there must be a union of those who cannot exist without each other; for example, of male and female, that the race may continue ; and this is a union which is formed, not of deliberate purpose, but I because, in common with other animals and with plants, man- / kind have a natural desire to leave behind them an image of % ' themselves. And 1(2) there must be a union of natural ruler and subject, that both may be preserved. For he who can foresee with his mind is by nature intended to be lord and master, and he who can work with his body is a subject, 3 and by nature a slave ; hence master and slave have the same 1252 b interest. Nature, however, has distinguished between the female and the slave. For she is not niggardly, like the ; smith who fashions the Delphian knife for many uses ; she makes each thing for a single use, and every instrument is best made when intended for one and not for many uses. 4 But among barbarians no distinction is made between women '^5' and slaves, because there is no natural ruler among them: they are a community of slaves, male and female. Wherefore the poets say, — 'It is meet that Hellenes should rule over barbarians'^;* ' Or, with Bernays, 'how the different kinds of lule differ from one another, and generally whether any scientific result can be attained about each one of them.' " Eurip. Iphig. in Aulid. 1400. Growth of the State 27 as if they thought that the barbarian and the slave were I. by nature one. Out of these two relationships between man and woman, 5 master and slave, the family liist arises, and Hesiod is right when he says, — - ' First house and wife and an ox for the plough^,' for the ox is the poor man's slave. The family is the associa- . tion established by nature for the supply of men's every-day | wants, and the members of it are called by Charondas ' com- | panions of the cupboard' [o/ioo-iTrvors], and by Epiraenides the Cretan, '* companions of the manger^' \ofxoKaiTovi\. But when several families are united, and the association-^" aims at something more than the supply of daily needs, then comes into existence the villa^. And the most natural ^ form of the village appears to be that of a colony from the family, composed of the children and grandchildren, who are said to be ' suckled with the same milk.' And this is the reason why Hellenic states were originally governed by kings ; because the Hellenes were under royal rule before v- they came together, as the barbarians still are. Every family is ruled by the eldest, and therefore in the colonies of the family the kingly form of government prevailed because they were of the same blood. As Homer says [of the 7 Cyclopes] : — ' Each one gives law to his children and to his wives ^.' For they lived dispersedly, as was the manner in ancient • Op. et Di. 405. ^ Or, reading with the old translator (William of Moerbek) ofxO' Kanvovs, ' companions of the hearth.' * Od. Ix. 114, quoted by Plato, Law?, iii. 6S0, and in N. Eth. x. 9. § 13. 2 8 Man a 'Political Animal I. 2 times. Wherefore men say that the Gods have a kino-, jbecause they themselves either are or were in ancient times |under the rule of a king. For they imagine, not only the ^forms of the Gods, but their ways of life to be like their own. ^ When several villages are united in a single community, perfect and large enough to be nearly or quite self-sufficing, the state comes into existence, originating in the bare needs , of life, and continuing in existence for the sake of a good ^life. And therefore, if the earlier forms of society are natural, so is the state, for it is the end of them, and the [completed] nature is the end. For what each thing is when fully developed, we call its nature, whether we are speaking 9 of a man, a horse, or a family. Besides, the final cause and .end of a thing is the best,^nd to be sdf-sufficina is the^ end 1253 4and the,best. — — .,.~..<...^. -....„,„„ ^lence it is evident that the state is a creation of nature, land that man is by nature ajgolitical animal. And he who by nature and not by mere accident is without a state, is either above humanity, or below it ; he is the ' Tribeless, lawless, hearthless one,' 10 whom Homer ^ denounces — the outcast who is a lover of war ; he may be compared to an unprotected piece in the game of draughts. Now the reason why man is more of a political animal than bees or any other gregarious animals is evident. Nature, as we often say, makes nothing in vain "^^ and man is the only animal whom she has endowed with the gift of 1 1 speech ^ And whereas mere sound is but an indication * 11. ix. 63. ^Cp. c. 8. §12. 3 cp yii_ j^. § 12. I 'Man a Political Animal 29 of pleasure or pain, and is therefore found in other animals I. 2 (for their nature attains to the perception of pleasure and pain and the intimation of them to one another, and no further), the power of speech is intended to set forth the expedient and inexpedient, and likewise the just and the unjust. And it is a characteristic of man that he alone la has any sense of good and evil, of just and unjust, and the ' association of living beings who have this sense makes a i family and a state. Thus the state is by nature clearly prior to the family . and to the individual, since the whole is of necessity 13 prior to the part; for example, if the whole body be destroyed, there will be no foot or hand, except in an Ch /i<^i '^i" equivocal sense, as we might speak of a stone hand ; for f/> ^ V^ when destroyed the hand will be no better. But things are defined by their working and power ; and we ought not to say that they are the same when they are no longer the same, but only that they have the same name. The 14 proof that the state is a creation of nature and prior to the individual is that the individual, when isolated, is not self- sufficing ; and therefore he is like a part in relation to the whole. But he who is unable to live in society, or who has no need because he is sufficient for himself, must be either a \ beast or a god : he is no part of a state. A social instinct is 1 5 implanted in all men by nature, and yet he who first founded ' the state was the greatest of benefactors. For man, when perfected, is the best of animals, but, when separated from law and justice, he is the worst of all ; since armed injustice 16 is the more dangerous, and he is equipped at birth with the arms of intelligence and with moral qualities which he may use for the worst ends. Wherefore, if he have not virtue, he 3 0 The Parts of the Household I. 2 is the most unholy and the most savage of animals, and the most ! full of lust and gluttony. But justice is the bond of men in states, and the administration of justice, which is the determina- tion of what is just ^ is the principle of order in political society. 3 Seeing then that the state is made up of households, before speaking of the state we must speak of the ^ management 1253 b of the household ^. The parts of the household are the persons who compose it, and a complete household consists s, of slaves and freemen. Now we should begin by examining everything in its least elements ; and the first and least parts of a family are master and slave, husband and wife, father and children. We have therefore to consider what each 2 of these three relations is and ought to be : — I mean the relation of master and servant, of husband and wife, and thirdly of parent and cliild. [I say ya^iiKi] and reKvoTiotrjTCKT], there being no words for the two latter notions which ade- 3 quately represent them.] And there is another element of a household, the so-called art of money-making, which, according to some, is identical with household management, according to others, a principal part of it ; the nature of this art will also have to be considered by us. Let us first speak of master and slave, looking to the needs of practical life and also seeking to attain some better 4 theory of their relation than exists at present. For some are of opinion that the rule of a master is a science, and that the management of a household, and the mastership of slaves, and the political and royal rule, as I was saying at the out- set', are all the same. Others affirm that the rule of a master 1 Cp. N. Eth. V. 6. § 4. ' Reading with the MSS. olKOVOfJ.ias. ° Plato in Pol. 258 E foil., referred to already in c. I. § 2. Slavery — Necessary 3 i over slaves is contrary to nature, and that the distinction I. 3 between slave and freeman exists by law only, and not by nature ; and being an interference with nature is therefore unjust. Property is a part of the household, and therefore the art 4 of acquiring property is a part of the art of managing the n< household ; for no man can live well, or indeed live at all, unless he be provided with necessaries. And as in the arts which have a definite sphere the workers must have their own proper instruments for the accomplishment of their work, so it is in the management of a household. Now, instruments a / i, L are of various sorts ; some are living, others lifeless ; in the 7 — : rudder, the pilot of a ship has a lifeless, in the look-out man, ^^ ULj^ a living instmment ; for in the arts the servant is a kind - ' of instrument. Thus, too, a possession is an instrument/ for maintaining life. And so, in the arrangement of the family, a slave is a living possession, and property a number of such instruments ; and the servant is himself an instrument, which takes precedence of all other instruments. For if 3 every instrument could accomplish its own work, obeying or anticipating the will of others, like the statues of Daedalus, or the tripods of Hephaestus, which, says the poet ', ' of their own accord entered the assembly of the Gods ' ; if, in like manner, the shuttle would weave and the plectrum touch the lyre without a hand to guide them, chief workmen would not want servants, nor masters slaves. Here, how- 1254 a ever, another distinction must be drawn : the instruments ^ commonly so called are instraments of production, whilst a possession is an instrument of action. The shuttle, for ' Kom. I!, xviii. 376. 3 2 Slavery — Is it also Natural^ I. 4 example, is not only of use, but something else is made by- it, whereas of a garment or of a bed there is only the use. Further, as production and action are different in kind, and both require instruments, the instruments which they 5 employ must likewise diifer in kind. But life is action land not pj-oduction, and therefore the slave is the minister of faction [for he ministers to his master's life]. Again, a possession is spoken of as a part is spoken of; for the part is not only a part of something else, but wholly belongs to it ; and this is also true of a possession. The master is only the master of the slave ; he does not belong to him, whereas the slave is not only the slave of his master, but wholly belongs to him. Hence we see what is the nature and office of a slave ; he who is by nature not his • own but another's and yet a man, is by nature a slave ; and he may be said to belong to another who, being a human being, is also a possession. And a possession may be 1 defined as an instrument of action, separable from the ' possessor. 6 But is there any one thus intended by nature to be a slave, sj^ and for whom such a condition is expedient and right, or rather is not all slavery a violation of nature ? There is no difficulty in answering this question, on 2 grounds both of reason and of fact. For that some should rule and others be ruled is a thing, not only necessary, but 1 expedient ; ;from the hour of their birth, some are marked out for subjection, others for rule. And whereas there are many kinds both of rulers and subjects, that rule is the better which is exercised over better subjects — for example, to rule over men is better than to rule over wild beasts. The work is better which is executed Slavery — Justified 3 3 by better workmen ; and where one man rules and another is I. 5 ruled, they may be said to have a work. In all things which form a composite whole and which are made up of parts, whether continuous or discrete, a distinction between the ruling and the subject element comes to light. Such a 4 duality exists in living creatures, but not in them only ; it originates in the constitution of the universe ; even in things which have no life, there is a ruling principle, as ^ in musical hai mony ^ But we are wandering from the subject. We will, therefore, restrict ourselves to the living creature which, in the first place, consists of soul and body : and of these two, the one is by nature the ruler, and the other the subject. But then we must look for the intentions 5 of nature in things which retain their nature, and not in things which are corrupted. And therefore we must study the man who is in the most perfect state both of body and soul, for in him we shall see the true relation of the two ; although in bad or corrupted natures the body will often 1254 b appear to rule over the soul, because they are in an evil and unnatural condition. First then we may observe in living 6 creatures both a despotical and a constitutional rule ; for the sod rules the body with a despotical rule, whereas the i|itel- [ lect rules the appetites with a constitutional and royal rule.' And it is clear that the rule of the soul over the body, and of the mind and the rational element over the passionate is natural and expedient ; whereas the equality of the two or the rule of the inferior is always hurtful. The same holds good 7 of animals as well as of men ; for tame animals have a better nature than wild, and all tame animals are better off" when they are ruled by man ; for then they are preserved. Again, ^ Or, ' of harmony [in music].' DAVIS D 34 Slavery — Both Sides of the ^lestion I. 5 the male is by nature superior, and the female inferior; and the one rules, and the other is ruled ; this principle, of gmecessity, extends to ali mankind. Where then there is such a difference as that between soul and body, or between men and animals (as in the case of those whose business is to use their body, and who can do nothing better), the lower sort are by nature slaves, and it is better for them as for all 9 inferiors that they should be under the rule of a master. For he who can be, and therefore is anothei's, and he who participates in reason enough to apprehend, but not to have, iKreason, is a slave by nature. Whereas the lower animals cannot even apprehend reason ; they obey their instincts. And indeed the use made of slaves and of tame animals is not very different ; for both with their bodies minister to ID the needs of life. Nature would like to distinguish betweei? the bodies of freemen and slaves, making the one strong for servile labour, the other upright, and although useless for such services, useful for political life in the arts both of war and peace. But this does not hold universally: for I some slaves have the souls and others have the bodies of '■ freemen. And doubtless if men differed from one another in the mere forms of their bodies as much as the statues of the Gods do from men, all would acknowledge that the inferior class 1 1 should be slaves of the superior. And if there is a difference in the body, how much more in the soul ! But the beauty of the 1255 a body is seen, whereas the beauty of the soul is not seen. It_is clear, then, that some men are by nature free, and others slaves, I and that for these latter slavery is both expedient and right. 6 But that those who take the opposite view have in a certain way right on their side, may be easily seen. For the words slavery and slave are used in two senses. There is a slave i ^'***''*^ \ ^""^ ft-'-re.^cX/- ,«y^«.r Slavery — Both Sides of the Question 3 y or slavery by law as well as by nature. The law of which I. 6 I speak is a sort of convention, according to which whatever is taken in war is supposed to belong to the victors. But a this right many jurists impeach, as they would an orator who brought forward an unconstitutional measure : they detest the notion that, because one man has the power of doing violence and is superior in brute strength, another shall be his slave and subject. Even among philosophers there is a difference of opinion. The origin of the dispute, and the reason why 3 the arguments cross, is as follows : Virtue, when furnished with means, may be deemed to have the greatest power of doing violence : and as superior power is only found where there is superior excellence of some kind, power is thought to imply virtue. But does it likewise imply justice ? — that is the question. And, in order to make a distinction between them, 4 some assert that justice is benevolence : to which others reply that justice is nothing more than the rule of a superior. If the two views are regarded as antagonistic and exclusive [i. e. if the notion that justice is benevolence excludes the idea of a just rule of a superior], the alternative [viz. that no one should rule over others ^] has no force or plausibility, because it implies that not even the superior in virtue ought to rule, or be master. Some, clinging, as they think, to a principle of 5 justice (for law and custom are a sort of justice), assume that slavery in war is justified by law, but they are not consistent. For what if the cause of the war be unjust ? No one would ever say that he is a slave who is unworthy to be a slave. Were this the case, men of the highest rank would be slaves and the children of slaves if they or their parents chance to have been taken captive and sold. Wherefore Hellenes do 6 * Cp. § 2. D 2 ^6 When Natural^ when 'Dnnafural I. 6 not like to call themselves slaves, but confine the term to ■^ barbarians. Yet, in using this language, they really mean the natural slave of whom we spoke at first ; for it must be admitted that some are slaves everywhere, others nowhere. 7 The same principle applies to nobility. Hellenes regard them- selves as noble everywhere, and not only in their own country, but they deem the barbarians noble only when at home, I thereby implying that there are two sorts of nobility and ;, freedom, the one absolute, the other relative. The Helen of Theodectes says : — ' Who would presume to call me servant who am on both sides sprung from the stem of the Gods ? ' 8 What does this mean but that they distinguish freedom and slavery, noble and humble birth, by the two principles of 1255 b good and evil ? They think that as men and animals beget i men and animals, so from good men a good man springs. I But this is what nature, though she may intend it, often fails to accomplish. 9 We see then that there is some foundation for this differ- ence of opinion, and that some actual slaves and freemen are not so by nature, and also that there is in some cases a marked distinction between the two classes, rendering it expedient and right for the one to be slaves and the others to be masters : the one practising obedience, the others exercising the autho- lo rity which nature intended them to have. The abuse of this authority is injurious to both ; for the inteiests of part and whole ', of body and soul, are the same, and the slave is a part of the master, a living but separated part of his bodily frame. Wheie the relation between them is natural they arc friends 1 Cp. c. 4. § 5. The T^iJe of the Household 37 and have a common interest, but where it rests merely on law I. and force the reverse is true. The previous remarks are quite enough to show that the 7 rule of a master is not a constitutional rule, and therefore that all the different kinds of rule are not, as some affirm, the same with each other ^ For there is one rule exercised over subjects who are by nature free, another over subjects who are by nature slaves. The rule of a household is a monarchy, for every house is under one head : whereas constitutional rule is a government of freemen and equals. The master is not 2 called a master because he has science, but because he is of a certain character, and the same remark applies to the slave and the freeman. Still there may be a science for the master and a science for the slave. The science of the slave would be such as the man of Syracuse taught, who made money by instructing slaves in their ordinary duties. And such a know- 3 ledge may be carried further, so as to include cookery and similar menial arts. For some duties are of the more neces- sary, others of the more honourable sort ; as the proverb says, ' slave before slave, master before master.' But all such 4 branches of knowledge are servile. There is likewise a science of the master, which teaches the use of slaves ; for the master as such is concerned, not with the acquisition, but with the use of them. Yet this so-called science is not anything great or wonderful ; for the master need only know how to order that which the slave must know how to execute. Hence those 5 who are in a position which places them above toil, have stewards who attend to their households while they occupy themselves with philosophy or with politics. But the art ot acquiring slaves, I mean of justly acquiring them, differs both ' Plato Pol. 25S E loll., referreii to already in c. I. § 2. 3 8 Property — What Place in the Household I. 7 from the art of the master and the art of the slave, being a species of hunting or war '. Enough of the distinction between master and slave. 1256 a Let us now enquire into property generally, and into the art of money-making, in accordance with our usual method [of resolving a whole into its parts ^], for a slave has been shown to be a part of property. The first question is whether the art of money-making is the same with the art of managing a household or a part of it, or instrumental to it ; and if the last, whether in the way that the art of making shuttles is instrumental to the art of weaving, or in the way that the casting of bronze is instrumental to the art of the statuary, for they are not instrumental in the same way, but the one pro- 2 vides tools and the other material ; and by material I mean the substratum out of which any work is made ; thus wool is the material of the weaver, bronze of the statuary. Now it is easy to see that the art of household management is not ^ identical with the art of money-making, for the one uses the I material which the other provides. And the art which uses household stores can be no other than the art of household management. There is, however, a doubt whether the art of money-making is a part of household management or a distinct 3 art. [They appear to be connected] ; for the money-maker has to consider whence money and property can be procured ; but there are many sorts of property and wealth :— there is husbandry and the care and provision of food in general ; are 4 these parts of the money-making art or distinct arts ? Again, there are many sorts of food, and therefore there are many kinds of lives both of animals and men ; they must all have food, and the differences in their food have made differences ' Cp. vii. 14. § 21. " Cp. c. I. § 3. Property— ]{ests on a Physical Basts 39 in their ways of life. For of beasts, some are gregarious, I. 8 others are soUtary ; they live in the way which is best adapted 5 to sustain them, accordingly as they are carnivorous or her- bivorous or omnivorous : and their habits are determined for them by nature in such a manner that they may obtain with greater facility the food of their choice. But, as different individuals have different tastes, the same things are not naturally pleasant to all of them ; and therefore the lives of carnivorous or herbivorous animals further differ among them- selves. In the lives of men too there is a great difference. 6 - The laziest are shepherds, who lead an idle life, and get their subsistence without trouble from tame animals; their flocks having to wander from place to place in search of pas- ture, they are compelled to follow them, cultivating a sort of living farm. Others support themselves by hunting, which is 7 of different kinds. Some, for example, are pirates, others, who dwell near lakes or marshes or rivers or a sea in which there are fish, are fishermen, and others live by the pursuit of birds or wild beasts. The greater number obtain a living from the fruits of the soil. Such are the modes of subsistence 8 which prevail among those ^ whose industry is employed immediately upon the products of nature ^, and whose food is not acquired by exchange and retail trade — there is the shep- 1256 b herd, the husbandman, the pirate, the fisherman, the hunter. Some gain a comfortable maintenance out of two employ- ments, eking out the deficiencies of one of them by another : thus the life of a shepherd may be combined with that of a brigand, the life of a farmer with that of a hunter. Other 9 modes of life are similarly combined in any way which the needs of men may require. Property, in the sense of a bare * Or, ' whose labour is personal.' 40 Property — Natural Acquisition I. 8 livelihood, seems to be given by nature herself to all, both 10 when they are first born, and when they are grown up. For some animals biing forth, together with their offspring, so much food as will last until they are able to supply themselves ; of this the vermiparous or oviparous animals are an instance ; and the viviparous animals have up to a certain time a supply of food for their young in themselves, which is called milk. 1 1 In like manner we may infer that, after the birth of animals, plants exist for their sake, and that the other animals exist for the sake of man, the tame for use and food, the wild, if not all, at least the greater part of them, for food, and for the 12 provision of clothing and various instruments. Now if nature makes nothing incomplete, and nothing in vain, the inference must be that she has made all animals and plants for the sake of man. And so, in one point of view, the art of war is a natural art of acquisition, for it includes hunting, an art which we ought to practise against wild beasts, and against men who, though intended by nature to be governed, will not submit ; for war of such a kind is naturally just ^. 13 Of the art of acquisition then there is one kind ^ which is natural and is a part of the managemenr^f a households Either we must suppose the necessaries of life to exist pre- viously, or the art of household management must provide a store of them for the common use of the family or state. 14 They are the elements of true wealth ; for the amount of property which is needed for a good life is not unlimited, although Solon in one of his poems says that, ' No bound to riches has been fixed for man '.* * Cp. c. 7. § 5, and vii. 14. § 21, 2 Or, with Bernays, ' which by nature is a part of the management of a household.' ^ Bergk, Poet. Lyr. Solon, 13. v. 71. Property — Money-making 41 But there is a boundary fixed, just as there is in the arts ; for I. 8 the instruments of any art are never unlimited, either in '5 number or size, and wealth may be defined as a number of \ instruments to be used in a household or in a state. And so I we see that there is a natural art of acquisition which is prac- tised by managers of households and by statesmen, and what is the reason of this. Theie is another variety of the art of acquisition which is 9 commonly and rightly called the art of making money, and 1257 a has in fact suggested the notion that wealth and property have no limit. Being nearly connected with the preceding, it is often identified with it. But though they are not very different, neither are they the same. The kind already described is given by nature, the other is gained by experience and art. Let us begin our discussion of the question with the fol- 2 lowing considerations : — Of everything which we possess there are two uses : both belong to the thing as such, but not in the same manner, for one is the proper, and the other the improper or secondary use of it. For example, a shoe is used for wear, and is used for exchange ; both are uses of the shoe. He who gives 3 a shoe in exchange for money or food to him who wants one, does indeed use the shoe as a shoe, but this is not its proper or primary purpose, for a shoe is not made to be an object of barter. The same may be said of all possessions, for the art of exchange extends to all of them, and it 4 arises at first in a natural manner from the circumstance that some have too little, others too much. Hence we may infer that retail trade is not a natural part of the art of money- ■ making ; had it been so, men would have ceased to exchange when they had enough. And in the first community, which 5 42 Property — Coined Mofiey 9 is the family, this art is obviously of no use, but only begins to be useful when the society increases. For the members of the family originally had all things in common ; in a more divided state of society they ' still shared in many things, but they were different things ^ which they had to give in ex- change for what they wanted, a kind of barter which is still 6 practised among barbarous nations who exchange with one another the necessaries of life and nothing more ; giving and receiving wine, for example, in exchange for corn and the (like. This sort of barter is not part of the money-making [art and is not contrary to nature, but is needed for the satis- 7 faction of men's natural wants. The other or more complex form of exchange grew out of the simpler. When the in- i habitants of one country became more dependent on those of another, and they imported what they needed, and exported 8 the surplus, money necessarily came into use. For the various necessaries of life are not easily carried about, and hence men agreed to employ in their dealings with each other something which was intrinsically useful and easily applicable to the purposes of life, for example, iron, silver, and the like. Of this the value was at first measured by size and weight, but in process of time they put a stamp upon it, to save the trouble of weighing and to mark the value. 1257 b When the use of coin had once been discovered, out of the " barter of necessary articles arose the other art of money- making, namely, retail trade ; which was at first probably a simple matter, but became more complicated as soon as men learned by experience whence and by what exchanges the 10 greatest profit might be made. Originating in the use of coin, the art of money-making is generally thought to be chiefly ' Or, more siniply, ' shared in many more things.' Property : True Notion of Wealth 43 concerned with it, and to be the art which produces wealth I. 0 and money ; having to consider how they may be accumulated. Indeed, wealth is assumed by many to be only a quantity of coin, because the art of money-making and retail trade are concerned with coin. Others maintain that coined money is ii a mere sham, a thing not natural, but conventional only, which would have no value or use for any of the purposes of daily life if another commodity were substituted by the users. And, indeed, he who is rich in coin may often be in want of >^ necessary food. But how can that be wealth of which a man may havs a great abundance and yet perish with hunger, like Midas in the fable, whose insatiable prayer turned everything that was set before him into gold ? Men seek after a better notion of wealth and of the art of 13 making money than the mere acquisition of coin, and they are right. For natural wealth and the natural art of money- i making are a different thing ; in their true form they are part of the management of a household ; whereas retail trade is the art of producing wealth, not in every way, but by exchange. And it seems to be concerned with coin ; for coin is the starting-point and the goal of exchange. And 13 there is no bound to the wealth which springs from this art of money-making ^ As in the art of medicine there is no limit to the pursuit of health, and as in the other arts there is no limit to the pursuit of their several ends, for they aim at accomplishing their ends to the uttermost; (but of the means there is a limit, for the end is always the limit), so, too, in this art of money-making there is no limit of the end, which is wealth of the spurious kind, and the acquisition of money. But the art of household management has a limit; i^ 1 Cp. c. 8, § 14. 44 '^ioney -making in Excess '\)nnatiiral I. 9 the unlimited acquisition of money is not its business. And, ; therefore, in one point of view, all wealth must have a limit ; h nevertheless, as a matter of fact, we find the opposite to be the case ; for all money-makers increase their hoard of coin without limit. The source of the confusion is the near 15 connexion between the two kinds of money-making; in either, the instrument [i. e. wealth] is the same, although the use is different, and so they pass into one another ; for each is a use V of the same property \ but with a difference : accumulation is \ the end in the one case, but there is a further end in the other. Hence some persons are led to believe that making money is the object of household management, and the whole idea of their lives is that they ought either to increase their money 16 without limit, or at any rate not to lose it. The origin of 1258 a this disposition in men is that they are intent upon living only, and not upon living well ; and, as their desires are unlimited, thev also desire that the means of gratifying them should be without limit. Even those who aim at a good life seek the means of obtaining bodily pleasures ; and, since the enjoyment of these appears to depend on property, they are absorbed in making money: and so there arises the second species of 17 money-making. For, as their enjoyment is in excess, they seek an art which produces the excess of enjoyment ; and, if they are not able to supply their pleasures by the art of money-making, they try other arts, using in turn every faculty in a manner contrary to nature. The quality of courage, for example, is not intended to make money, but to inspire con- fidence; neither is this the aim of the general's or of the physician's art ; but the one aims at victory and the other at 18 health. Nevertheless, some men turn every quality or art ' Reading KTqctaiz xpf, Cp. c. 8. § lo. * Or, ' We are free to speculate about them, but in practice we are limited by circumstances.' (Bernays.) K^nds of Money-making 47 and which pay best in particular places, for some do better in 1. 11 one place and some in another. Secondly, husbandry, which ^ may be either tillage or planting, and the keeping of bees and of fish, or fowl, or of any animals which may be useful to man. These are the divisions of the true or proper art of 3 money- making and come first. Of the other, which consists in exchange, the first and most important division is commerce | (of which there are three kinds — commerce by sea, commerce \ by land, selling in shops — these again differing as they are ' safer or more profitable), the second is ^ usuryj the third, service for hire — of this, one kind is employed in the 4 mechanical arts, the other in unskilled and bodily labour. There is still a third sort of money-making intermediate ':' between this and the first or natural mode which is partly natural, but is also concerned with exchange of the fruits and other products of the earth. Some of these latter, although they bear no fruit, are nevertheless profitable; for example, wood and minerals. The art of mining, by which minerals 5 are obtained, has many branches, for there are various kinds of things dug out of the earth. Of the several divisions of money-making I now speak generally; a minute considera- tion of them might be useful in practice, but it would be tiresome to dwell upon them at greater length nov/. Those occupations are most truly arts in which there is 5 the least element of chance ; they are the meanest in which the body is 'most deteriorated, the most servile in which there : is the greatest use of the body, and the illiberal in which there is the least need of excellence. Works have been written upon these subjects by various 7 persons; for example, by Chares the Parian, and Apollodorus the Lemnian, who have treated of Tillage and Planting, 48 Economic Tales I. 11 while others have treated of other branches ; any one who 1259 a cares for such matters may refer to their writings. It would be well also to collect the scattered stories of the ways in which individuals have succeeded in amassing a fortune; 8 for all this is useful to persons who value the art of making money. There is the anecdote of Thales the Milesian and his financial device, which involves a principle of universal application, but is attributed to him on account of his reputa- 9 tion for wisdom. He was reproached for his poverty, which was supposed to show that philosophy was of no use. According to the story, he knew by his skill in the stars while it was yet winter that there would be a great harvest of olives in the coming year ; so, having a little capital, he gave earnest-money for the use of all the olive-presses in Chios and Miletus, which he hired at a low price because no one bid against him. When the harvest-time came, and many wanted them all at once and of a sudden, he let them out at any rate which he pleased, and made a quantity of money. Thus he showed the world that philosophers can easily be rich if 10 they like, but that their ambition is of another sort. He is supposed to have given a striking proof of his wisdom, but, as I was saying, his device for getting money is of universal application, and is nothing but the creation of a monopoly. It is an art often practised by cities when they are in want of money ; they make a monopoly of provisions. 11 There was a man of Sicily, who, having money deposited with him, bought up all the iron from the iron mines ; after- wards, when the merchants from their various markets came to buy, he was the only seller, and without much increasing 12 the price he gained 200 per cent. Which when Dionysius heard, he told him that he might take away his money, but Household Government 49 that he must not remain at Syracuse, for he thought that the I- H man had discovered a way of making money which was injurious to his own interests. He had the same idea ' as Thales ; they both contrived to create a monopoly for them- selves. And statesmen ought to know these things ; for a 13 state is often as much in want of money and of such devices for obtaining it as a household, or even more so ; hence some public men devote themselves entirely to finance. Of household management we have seen ^ that there are 12 three parts — one is the rule of a master over slaves, which has been discussed already ', another of a father, and the_^ third of a husband. A husband and father rules over wifej and children, both free, but the rule differs, the rule over' his children being a royal, over his wife^a^oginstitutipnal rule. 1259 b For although there may be exceptions to the order of nature,-" the male is by nature fitter for command than the female, just ^ as the elder and full-grown is superior to the younger and more immature. But in most constitutional states the citizens 2 rule and are ruled by turns, for the idea of a constitutional state implies that the natures of the citizens are equal, and do not differ at all *. Nevertheless, when one rules and the other is ruled we endeavour to create a difference of outward forms and modes of address and titles of respect, which may be illustrated by the saying of Amasis about his foot-pan ^. The relation of the male to the female is of this kind, but 3 there the inequality is permanent. The rule of a father over j his children is royal, for he receives both love and the respect ' due to age, exercising a kind of royal power. And therefore ^ Reading evprjfia with Bernays. ^ Cp. c. 3. § i. ^ Cp. c. 3-7. ■• Cp. ii. 2. § 6; iii. 17. § 4. * Herod, ii. 172, and note on this passage. DAVIS E JO Virtue in the Subject Classes 1. 12 Homer has appropriately called Zeus ' father of Gods and men,' because he is the king of them all. For a king is the natural superior of his subjects, but he should be of the same kin or kind with them, and such is the relation of elder and younger, of father and son. 13 Thus it is clear that household management attends more to men than to the acquisition of inanimate things, and to human excellence more than to the excellence of property which we call wealth, and to the virtue of freemen more than a to the virtue of slaves. A question may indeed be raised, whether there is any excellence at all in a slave beyond merely instrumental and ministerial qualities — whether he can have the virtues of temperance, courage, justice, and tlie like ; or whether slaves possess only bodily and ministerial qualities. And, whichever way we answer the question, a difficulty 3 arises ; for, if they have virtue, in what will they differ from freemen ? On the other hand, since they are men and share in reason, it seems absurd to say that they have no virtue. A similar question may be raised about women and children, whether they too have virtues : ought a woman to be tem- perate and brave and just, and is a child to be called temperate, 4 and intemperate, or not ? So in general we may ask about the natural ruler, and the natural subject, whether they have the same or different virtues. For a noble nature is equally required in both, but if so, why should one of them always rule, and the other always be ruled .'' Nor can we say that this is a question of degree, for the difference between ruler . and subject is a difference of kind, and therefore not of degree ; yet how strange is the supposition that the one 5 ought, and that the other ought not, to have virtue ! For if the ruler is intemperate and unjust, how can he rule well ? yirtues not the same for All 5- 1 if the subject, how can he obey well ? If he be licentious I. 13 and cowardly, he will certainly not do his duty. It is evident, .^'-^^^ * therefore, that both of them must have a share of virtue, but varying according to their various natures. And this is at 6 once indicated by the soul, in which one part naturally rules, and the other is subject, and the virtue of the ruler we main- tain to be different from that of the subject ; — the one being the virtue of the rational, and the other of the irrational part. Now, it is obvious that the same principle applies generally, and therefore almost all things rule and are ruled according to nature. But the kind of rule differs ; — the freeman rules over 7 the slave after another manner from that in which the male rules over the female, or the man over the child ; although the parts of the soul are present in all of them, they are pre- sent in different degrees. For the slave has no deliberative % faculty at all ; the woman has, but it is ^ without authority ^, and the child has, but it is immature. So it must necessarily 8 be with the moral virtues also ; all may be supposed to partake of them, but only in such manner and degree as is required by each for the fulfilment of his duty. Hence the ruler ought to have moral virtue in perfection, for his duty is entirely that of a master artificer, and the master artificer is reason ; the subjects, on the other hand, require only that measure of virtue which is proper to each of them. Clearly, then, moral 9 ^*-\ lo^. virtue belongs to all of them ; but the temperance of a man ' and of a woman, or the courage and justice of a man and of a woman, are not, as Socrates maintained'-, the same; the( courage of a man is shown in commanding, of a woman in '■ obeying. And this holds of all other virtues, as will be more 10 clearly seen if we look at them in detail, for those who say * Or, with Bernays, ' incoixlusive.' 2 pjajo Meno, 71-73. E 2 f2 The Slave and the Artisan I. 13 generally that virtue consists in a good disposition of the soul, or in doing rightly, or the like, only deceive themselves. Far better than such definitions is their mode of speaking, 11 who, like Georgias ^, enumerate the virtues. All classes must be deemed to have their special attributes ; as the poet says of women, 'Silence is a woman's glory'',' but this is not equally the glory of man. The child is imper- fect, and therefore obviously his virtue is not relative to him- 12 self alone, but to the perfect man and to his teacher^, and in like manner the virtue of the slave is relative to a master. Now we determined that a slave is useful for the wants of lllife, and therefore he will obviously require only so much s virtue as will prevent him from failing in his duty through cowardice and intemperance. Some one will ask whether, if what we are saying is true, virtue will not be required also in the artisans, for they often fail in their work through miscon- 13 duct. But is there not a great difference in the two cases? For the slave shares in his master's life ; the artisan is less closely connected with him, and only attains excellence in proportion as he becomes a slave, [i. e. is under the direction of a master]. The meaner sort of mechanic has a special 1280 b and separate slavery; and whereas the slave exists by nature, 14 not so the shoemaker or other artisan. It is manifest, then^ fthat the master ought to be the source of excellence in the slave ; but not merely because he possesses the art which trains him in his duties *. Wherefore they are mistaken who forbid us to converse with slaves and say that we should employ * Plato Meno, 71-73. ^ Soph. Aj. 293. * ' His father who guides him ' (Bernays), * Cp. c. 7. § 4. End of Preliminary Enquiry 5-3 command only *, for slaves stand even more in need of admoni- I. 13 tion than children. The relations of husband and wife, parent and child, their 15 several virtues, what in their intercourse with one another is good, and what is evil, and how we may pursue the good and escape the evil, will have to be discussed when we speak of the different forms of government. For, inasmuch as every family is a part of a state, and these relationships are the parts of a family, the virtue of the part must have regard to the virtue of the whole. And therefore women and children must be trained by education with an eye to the state "^^ if the virtues of either of them are supposed to make any difference in the virtues of the state. And they must make a difference : 16 for the children grow up to be citizens, and lialf the free persons in a state are women ^. Of these matters, enough has been said ; of what remains, 14 let us speak at another time. Regarding, then, our present enquiry as complete, we will make a new beginning. And, first, let us examine the various theories of a perfect state. ^ Plato Laws, vi. 777. * Cp. v. 9. §§ 11-15 ; viii. i. § i, ' Plato Laws, vi. 781 n. 0\ (K**W ^ * BOOK lJ/%,/^ hi) II. 1 Our purpose is to consider what form of political commu- nity is best of all for those who are most able to realize their ideal of life. We must therefore examine not only this but other constitutions, both such as actually exist in well-governed states, and any theoretical forms which are held in esteem ; that what is good and useful may be brought to light. And let no one suppose that in seeking for something beyond them ^ we at all want to philosophize at the expense of truth ^ ; we only undertake this enquiry because all the constitutions with which we are acquainted are faulty. 2 We will begin with the natural beginning of the subject. Three alternatives are conceivable : The members of a state » must either have (i) all things or (2) nothing in common, or ' (3) some things in common and some not. That they should have nothing in common is clearly impossible, for the state is a community, and must at any rate have a common place — 126.1 a one city will be in one place, and the citizens are those who 3 share in that one city. But should a well-ordered state have all things, as far as may be, in common, or some only and not others ? For the citizens might conceivably have wives and children and property in common, as Socrates proposes in the Republic of Plato ^. Which is better, our present condition, or the proposed new order of society ? ^ Or, as Bcrnavs, taking iravrco? with aocJH^eaOat PovXofiivwv, ' we are anxious to make a sophistical display at any cost.' * Rep. V. -157 c. ^•»-\y Jl^Hti,H^ ■ Lrvu.rnu.it.caut U\. K^lf^., False Conception of Unity yy There are many difficulties in the community of women. II. 2 The principle on which Socrates rests the necessity of such /^^ an institution does not appear to be established by his argu- niei^ ; and then again as a means to the end which he ascribes to the state, takeu literally, it is impossible, and how we are to limit and qualify it is nowhere precisely stated. I am speak- a ing of the premiss from which the argument of Socrates pro- ceeds, 'that the greater the unity of the state the better.' Is Ch it not obvious that a state may at length attain such a degree g*://. cA. S §li. of unity as to be no longer a state ? — since the nature of a "T ' state is to be a plurality, and in tending to greater unity, from being a state, it becomes a family, and from being a family, an individual ; for the family may be said to be more one than the state, and the individual than the family. So that we ought not to attain this greatest unity even if we could, for it would be the destruction of the state. Again, a state is 3 •_ ^ not made up only of so many men, but of different kinds of men ; for similars do not constitute a state. It is not like a military alliance, of which the usefulness depends upon its quantity even where there is no difference in quality. Foi in that mutual protection is the end aimed at; and the question is the same as about the scales of a balance : which is the heavier ? In like manner, a state differs from a nation, whenever in a nation the people are not dispersed in villages, but are in the condition of the Arcadians ; in a state the elements out of which the unity is to be formed differ in kind. Wherefore 4 the principle of reciprocity \ as I have already remarked in the Ethics ^, is the salvation of states. And among freemen and equals this is a principle which must be maintained, for * Or, ' reciprocal proportion.' ' N. Eth. v. S. § 6. j'6 Plato's 1{epuhlic: II. 2 they cannot all rule together, but must change at the end of a year or some other period of time or in some order of suc- 5 cession. The result is that upon this plan they all govern ; [but the manner of government is] just as if shoemakers and carpenters were to exchange their occupations, and the same persons did not always continue shoemakers and carpenters. 6 And it is clearly better that, as in business, so also in politics (there should be continuance of the same persons where this 1261 b'is possible. But where this is not possible by reason of the natural equality of the citizens, and it would be unjust that any one should be excluded from the government (whether to govern be a good thing or a bad ^), then it is better, instead of all holding power, to adopt a principle of rotation, equals giving place to equals, as the oi'iginal rulers gave place 7 to them ^. Thus the one party inile and the others are ruled in turn, as if they were no longer the same persons. In like manner there is a variety in the offices held by them. Hence it is evident that a city is not by nature one in that sense which some persons affirm ; and that what is said to be the greatest good of cities is in reality their destruction ; but surely the good of things must be that which preserves them ^. 8 Again, in another point of view, this extreme unification , of the state is clearly not good ; for a family is more self- j sufficing than an individual, and a city than a family, and I a city only comes into being when the community is large \ enough to be self-sufficing. If then self-sufficiency is to be desired, the lesser degree of unity is more desirable than the greater. 8 But, even supposing that it were best for the community to 1 Cp.Pl. Rep. i. 345-6. ^ Cp. i. 12. § 2; iii. 17. § 4. » Cp. PI, Rep. i. 352. False Conception of %)nity S7 have the greatest degree of unity, this unity is by no means II. 3 indicated by the fact 'of all men saying "mine" and "not mine" at the same instant of time,' which, according to Socrates \ is the sign of perfect unity in a state. For the 2 word ' all ' is ambiguous. If the meaning be that every indi- vidual says ' mine ' and ' not mine ' at the same time, then perhaps the result at which Socrates aims may be in some degree accomplished ; each man will call the same person his own son and his own wife, and so of his property and of all that belongs to him. This, however, is not the way in which people would speak who had their wives and children in common ; they would say ' all ' but not ' each.' In like man- 3 ner their property would be described as belonging to them, not severally but collectively. There is an obvious fallacy in the term 'all': like some other words, 'both,' 'odd,' 'even,' it is ambiguous, and in argument becomes a source of logical puzzles. That all persons call the same thing mine in the sense in which each does so may be a fine thing, but it is impracticable ; or if the words are taken in the other sense [i. e. the sense which distinguishes ' all ' from ' each '], such a unity in no way conduces to harmony. And there is 4 another objection to the proposal. For that which is common to the greatest number has the least care bestowed upon it. Every one thinks chiefly of his own, hardly at all of they, common interest ; and only when he is himself concerned as an individual. For besides other considerations, everybody is more inclined to neglect the duty which he expects another to J fulfil ; as in families many attendants are often less useful than a few. Each citizen will have a thousand sons who will not 5 be his sons individually, but anybody will be equally the son 1 PI. Rep. V. 462 c. J- 8 Plato's Republic: II. 3 of anybody, and will therefore be neglected by all alike. Further, upon this principle, every one will call another ' mine ' or ' not mine ' according as he is prosperous or the reverse; — however small a fraction he may be of the whole number, he will say of every individual of the thousand, or whatever be the number of the city, ' such a one is mine,' ' such a one his ' ; and even about this he will not be posi- tive ; for it is impossible to know who chanced to have a child, or whether, if one came into existence, it has survived. 6 But which is better — to be able to say ' mine ' about every one of the two thousand or the ten thousand citizens, or to use the word ' mine ' in the ordinary and more restricted 7 sense ? For usually the same person is called by one man his son whom another calls his brother or cousin or kinsman or blood-relation or connexion by marriage either of himself or of some relation of his, and these relationships he distin- guishes from the tie which binds him to his tribe or ward ; land how much better is it to be the real cousin of somebody 8 than to be a son after Plato's fashion ! Nor is there any way of preventing brothers and children and fathers and mothers from sometimes recognizing one another; for chil- dren are born like their parents, and they will necessarily be 9 finding indications of their relationship to one another. Geo- graphers declare such to be the fact ; they say that in Upper Libya, where the women are common, nevertheless the chil- dren who are born are assigned to their respective fathers on the ground of their likeness ^. And some women, like the females of other animals — for example mares and cows — have a strong tendency to produce offspring resembling their * Cp. Herod, iv. iSo. Com muni ty of Women and Children fp parents, as was the case with the Pharsalian mare called II. 3 Dicaea (the Just)^ Other evils, against which it is not easy for the authors of 4 such a community to guard, will be assaults and homicides, voluntary as well as involuntary, quarrels and slanders, all which are most unholy acts when committed against fathers and mothers and near relations, but not equally unholy when there is no relationship. Moreover, they are much more likely to occur if the relationship is unknown, and, when they have occurred,! the customary expiations of them cannot v be made. Again, how strange it is that Socrates, after ' having made the children common, should hinder lovers from carnal intercourse only, but should permit familiarities between father and son or between brother and brother, than which nothing can be more unseemly, since even without them, love of this sort is improper. How strange, 3 too, to forbid intercourse for no other reason than the violence , of the pleasure, as though the relationship of father and son or of brothers with one another made no difference. This community of wives and children seems better 4 suited to the husbandmen than to the guardians, for if they have wives and children in common, they will be bound 126-2 b to one another by weaker ties, as a subject class should be, and they will remain obedient and not rebeP. In a word, the, 5 result of such a law would be just the opposite of that which ^ good laws ought to have, and the intention of Socrates 1 in making these regulations about women and children would ' defeat itself. For friendship we believe to be the greatest good of states ^ and the preservative of them against revolutions ; ^ Cp. Hist. Anim, vii. 6, p. 5S6 a. 13. » Cp, vii. 10. § 13. ' Cp. N. Eth. viii. i. § 4. i ^■ Li^i -• (i^(aI£Xiouo,^^i^'^' 'f^^^^ ^^'^^'^^^ II, <^o Plato's l{epublic: 4 neither is there anything which Socrates so greatly lauds as the unity of the state which he and all the world declare ^to be created by friendship. But the unity which he com- mends ^ would be like that of the lovers in the Sympo- sium^, who, as Aristophanes says, desire to grow together in the excess of their affection, and from being two to 7 become one, in which case one or both would certainly perish. Whereas [the very opposite will really happen ;] in a state having women and children common, love will be watery; and the father will certainly not say 'my son,' or 8 the son ' my father ■''.' As a little sweet wine mingled with I a great deal of water is imperceptible in the mixture, so, ' in this sort of community, the idea of relationship which ■r is based upon these names will be lost ; there is no reason why the so-called father should care about the son, or the son about the father, or brothers about one another. 9 Of the two qualities which chiefly inspire regard and affection ; — that a thing is your own and that you love it — neither 1 can exist in such a state as this. Again, the transfer of children as soon as they are born from the rank of husbandmen or of artisans to that of guardians, and from the rank of guardians into a lower rank ^, will be very difficult to arrange ; the givers or transferrers cannot but know whom they are giving and transferring, and 10 to whom. And the previously mentioned evils, such as assaults, unlawful loves, homicides, will happen more often amongst those who are transferred to the lower classes, or who have a place assigned to them among the guardians ; for they will no longer call the members of any other class * Cp. c. 2. * Symp. 189-193. ^ Cp. c. 3. * Rep. iii. 415. Community of Property 61 brothers, and children, and fathers, and mothers, and will II. 4 not, therefore, be afraid of committing any crimes by reason of consanguinity. Touching the community of wives and children, let this be our conclusion. Next let us consider what should be our arrangements 5 K^^f- about property : should the citizens of the perfect state have their possessions in common or not ? This question may 2 be discussed separately from the enactments about women and children. Even supposing that the women and children 1268 a belong to individuals, according to the custom which is at present universal, may there not be an advantage in having and using possessions in common ? Three cases are possible : (l) the soil may be appropriated, but the produce may be| ii^Mi»r U' < thrown for consumption into the common stock; and this is the practice of some nations. Or (2), the soil may be common, and may be culti\ated in common, but the produce divided among individuals for their private use ; this is a form of common property which is said to exist among certain barbarians. Or (3), the soil and the produce may be alike common. When the husbandmen are not the citizens, the case will 3 be different and easier to deal with ; but when the citizens till the ground themselves the question of ownership will give a world of trouble. If they do not sliare equally in enjoyments and toils, those who labour much and get little will necessarily complain of those who labour little and receive or consume much. The^e^is always a difficulty in men living together and 4 having things in common, but especially in their having common property. The partnerships of fellow-travellers are an example to the point ; for they generally fall out by the way and quarrel about any trifle which turns up. So 6z Plato's J^epublic: II. 5 with servants : we are most liable to take offence at those i with whom we most frequently come into contact in daily :iife. 6 These are only some of the disadvantages which attend the community of property ; the present arrangement, if im- proved as it might be by good customs and laws, would be far better, and would have the advantages of both systems. I Property should be in a certain sense common, but, as a '' 6 general rule, private ; for, when every one has a distinct ti cU^t fiDtAno ^ interest ^, men will not complain of one another, and they weiwV««^ C^M.^Wl make more progress, because every one will be attending to his own business. And yet among the good, and in respect of use, ' Friends,' as the proverb says, 'will have all things common ^' Even now there are traces of such a principle, showing that it is not impracticable, but, in well- ordered states, exists already to a certain extent and may 7 be carried further. For, although every man has his own property, some things he will place at the disposal of his friends, while of others he shares the use with them. The Lacedaemonians, for example, use one another's slaves, and horses and dogs, as if they were their own ; and when they happen to be in the country, they appropiiate in the fields 8 whatever provisions they want. It is clearly better that property > should be private, but the use of it common ;_and the special business of the legislator is to create in men this benevolent '* i disposition. Again, how immeasurably greater is the pleasure, ^CWt't t j263 b when a man feels a thing to be his own ; for the love of self " ^fy**- */*-''* **^ is a feeling implanted by nature and not given in vain, ■i^efj jfi^nsoo-^ '^g' although selfishness is rightly censured ; this, however, is not ' Cp. Rep. ii. 374. ^ Cp. Rep. iv. 424 a. ' Cp. N. Eth. ix. 8. § 6. Community of Property 6^ the mere love of self, but the love of self in excess, like II. 5 the miser's love of money ; for all, or almost all, men love money, and other such objects in a measure. And further, there is the greatest pleasure in doing a kindness or service to friends or guests or companions, which can only be rendered when a man has private property. The advantage is lost by 10 the excessive unification of the state. Two virtues are annihilated in such a state : first, temperance towards women 0^ (for it is an honourable action to abstain from another's wife : for temperance sake); secondly, liberality in the matter of ■4- property. No one, when men have all things in common, will any longer set an example of liberality or do any liberal action ; for liberality consists in the use which is made >> of property ^. Such legislation may have a specious appearance of 11 benevolence ; men readily listen to it, and are easily induced to believe that in some wonderful manner everybody will become everybody's friend, especially when some one ^ is heard denouncing the evils now existing in states, suits about contracts, convictions for perjury, flatteries of rich men and the like, which are said to arise out of the possession of private property. These evils, however, are due to a very 12 different cause — the wickedness of human nature. Indeed, we see that there is much more quarrelling among those | who have all things in common, though there are not many of them when compared with the vast numbers who have private property. Again, we ought to reckon, not only the evils from 13 -^ which the citizens will be saved, but also the advantages which they will lose. The life which they are to lead appears » Cp. N. Eth. iv. i.§ I. » Rep V. 464, 465. <^4 Plato''s T{epublic: II. 5 to be quite impracticable. The error of Socrates must be attributed to the false notion of unity from which he starts. 14 Unity there should be, both of the family and of the state, but in some respects only. For there is a point at which a state may attain such a degree of unity as to be no longer a state, or at which, without actually ceasing to exist, it will become an inferior state, like harmony passing into unison, 15 or rhythm which has been reduced to a single foot. The Istate^ as I was saying, is a plurality ^, which should be ■ junited and made into a community by education ; and it is strange that the author of a system of education, which he thinks will make the state virtuous, should expect to improve his citizens by regulations of this sort, and not by philosophy or by customs and laws, like those which prevail at Sparta and Crete respecting common meals, where- 1264 a by the legislator has [to a certain degree] made property 16 common. Let us remember that we should not disregard the experience of ages ; in the multitude of years these things, if they were good, would certainly not have been unknown ; for almost everything has been found out, although sometimes they are not put together ; in other cases men do not use the 1 7 knowledge which they have. Great light would be thrown on this subject if we could see such a form of government in the actual process of construction ; for the legislator could not form a state at all without distributing and dividing the citizens into associations for common meals, and into phratries and tribes. But all this legislation ends only in forbidding agriculture to the guardians, a prohibition which the Lace- daemonians try to enforce already. A.. 18 Again, Socrates has not said, nor is it easy to decide, ^ Cp. c. 2. § 2. Miscellaneous Criticisms 6y what in such a community will be the general form of the II. state. The citizens who are not guardians are the majority, \ and about them nothing has been determined : are the husbandmen, too, to have their property in common ? Or, besides the common land which he tills, is each individual to have his own ? and are their wives and children to be individual or common ? If, like the guardians, they are to 19 have all things in common, in what do they differ from them, or what will they gain by submitting to their government ? Or, upon what principle would they submit, unless indeed the governing class adopt the ingenious policy of the Cretans, who give their slaves the same institutions as their own, but forbid them gymnastic exercises and the possession of arms. If, on the other hand, the inferior classes are too 20 like other cities in respect of marriage and property, what will be the form of the community? Must it not contain two states in one ^, each liostile to the other ? ^ One class will consist of the guardians, who are a sort of watchmen ; another, of the husbandmen, and there will be the artisans and the other citizens ^. But [if so] the suits and quarrels, and all 21 the evils which Socrates affirms ^ to exist in other states, will exist equally among them. He says indeed that, having so good an education, the citizens will not need many laws, for example, laws about the city or about the markets * ; but then he confines his education to the guardians. Again, he makes 23 the husbandmen owners of the land upon condition of their paying a tribute •\ But in that case they are likely to be much 1 Cp. Rep. iv. 422 E. ' Or (with Bernays), ' He makes the guardians into a mere occupying garrison, while the husbandmen and artisans and the rest are the real citizens ; ' see note. s Rep. V. 464, 465. • Rep. iv. 425 D. 5 ]^gp_ y ^q^ ^^ DAVIS F 66 Plato's I{epuhlic II. 5 more unmanageable and conceited than the Helots, or 23 Penestae, or slaves in general \ And whether community of wives and property be necessary for the lower equally with the higher class or not, and the questions akin to this, what will be the education, form of government, laws of the lower class, Socrates has nowhere determined : neither is it easy, though very Important, to discover what should be the character of the Inferior classes, if the common life of the guardians Is to be maintained. ^ 12G4 b Again, if Socrates makes the women common, and retains ^4|private property, the men will see to the fields, but who will see to the house ? " And what will happen if the agricultural class have both their property and their wives in common ^ ? Once more ; it is absurd to argue, from the analogy of the animals, that men and women should follow the same pursuits ^ ; for animals have not to manage 25 a household. The government, too, as constituted by Socrates, contains elements of danger ; for he makes the same persons always rule. And if this Is often a cause of dis- turbance among the meaner sort, how much more among high- 26 spirited warriors ? But that the persons whom he makes rulers must be the same Is evident ; for the gold which the God mingles In the souls of men is not at one time given to one, at another time to another, but always to the same : as he says, * God mingles gold in some, and silver in others, from their very birth ; but brass and iron in those who are 27 meant to be artisans and husbandmen *.' Again, he deprives ' the guardians of happiness, and says that the legislator ought to make the whole state happy*. But the whole cannot ' Cp. c. 9. § 2. ^ These words are bracketed by Bekker. * Cp. Rtp. V. 451 D. * Cp. Rep. iii, 415 a. ^ Rep. iv. 419, 420. Criticisms 67 be happy unless most, or all, or some of its parts enjoy II. 5 happiness ^ In this respect happiness is not like the even principle in numbers, which may exist only in the whole, but in none of the parts ; not so happiness. And if the 28 guardians are not happy, who are ? Surely not the artisans or the common people. The Republic of which Socrates discourses has all these difficulties, and others quite as great. The same, or nearly the same, objections apply to Plato's 6 later work, the Laws, and therefore we had better examine briefly the constitution which is therein described. In the Republic, Socrates has definitely settled in all a few questions only; such as the community of women and children, the community of property, and the constitution of the state. The population is divided into two classes — one of husband- 2 men, and the other of warriors ; from this latter is taken a third class of counsellors and rulers of the state. But 3 Socrates has not determined whether the husbandmen and artisans are to have a share in the government, and whether they, too, are to carry arms and share in military service, or not. He certainly thinks that the women ought to share in the education of the guardians, and to fight by their side. The remainder of tJie work is filled up with digressions foreign to the main subject, and with discussions about the education of the guardians. In the Laws there is hardly l'-C5 a anything but laws; not much is said about the constitution. '^ This, which he had intended to make more of the ordinary type, he gradually brings round to the other or ideal form. For with the exception of the community of women and 5 property, he supposes everything to be the same in both 1 Cp. vii. 9. § 7. F 2 6^ Plato's Laws: II. 6 states ; there is to be the same education ; the citizens of both are to live free from servile occupations, and there are to be common meals in both. The only difference is that in the Laws, the common meals are extended to women ^, and the warriors number about 5000^, but in the Republic only 1000^, "»' 6 The discourses of Socrates are never commonplace ; they always exhibit grace and originality and thought ; but perfec- tion in everything can hardly be expected. We must not overlook the fact that the number of 5000 citizens, just now mentioned, will require a territory as large as Babylonia, or some other huge country, if so many persons are to be sup- ported in idleness, together with their women and attendants, jt who will be a multitude many times as great. [In framing (an ideal] we may assume what we wish, but should avoid \ impossibilities *, ««*«!«' It is said [in the Laws] that the legislator ought to have his eye directed to two points, — the people and the country ®. But neighbouring countries also must not be forgotten by him*, if the state for which he legislates is to have a true political life ''. For a state must have such a military force as will be serviceable against her neighbours, and not merely 8 useful at home. Even if the life of action is not admitted to be the best, either for individuals or states ^, still a city should be formidable to enemies, whether invading or retreating. There is another point ; Should not the amount of pro- perty be defined in some clearer way ? For Socrates says ^ Laws, vi. 781. " Laws, v. 737 E. * Rep, iv. 423 A (but see note on this passage). * Cp. vii. 4. § 2. ^ Perhaps Laws, 703-707 and 747 d (?). * Cp. c. 7. § 14. ' Cp. vii. 6. § 7. ' Cp. vii. c. 2 and 3. Criticisms <^9 that a man should have so much property as will enable him II. 6 to live temperately \ which Is only a way of saying ' to live well ' ; this would be the higher or more general conception. But a man may live temperately and yet miserably. A better 9 definition would be that a man must have so much property., as will enable him to live not only temperately but liberally ^ ; j if the two are parted, liberality will combine with luxury ; toil will be associated with temperance. For liberality and tem- perance are the only virtues ' which have to do with the use of property. A man cannot use property with mildness or courage, but temperately and liberally he may ; and therefore the practice of these virtues is inseparable from property. There is an inconsistency, too, in equalizing the property and lo ,.,^ not regulating the number of the citizens * ; the population is to remain unlimited, and he thinks that it will be sufficiently equalized by a certain number of marriages being unfruitful, however many are born to others, because he finds this to be 1265 b the case in existing states. But [in Plato's imaginary state] 1 1 greater care will be required than now ; for among ourselves, whatever may be the number of citizens, the property is always distributed among them, and therefore no one is in want ; but, if the property were incapable of division [as in the Laws], the supernumeraries, whether few or many, would get nothing. One would have thought that it was even more necessary to 12 limit population than property ; and that the limit should be fixed by calculating the chances of mortality in the children, and of sterility in married persons. The neglect of this sub- 1 3 ject, which in existing states is so common, is a never-failing ^ Laws, V. 737 D. ^ Cp. vii. 5. § i. ^ Omitling i^iis and reading dpirai with the MSS., or, reading with Bekk. i^iis aipirai, ' eligible qualities.' * But see Laws, v. 740. 70 Plato's Laws: II. 6 cause of poverty among the citizens ; and poverty is the parent of revolution and crime. Pheidon the Corinthian, who was one of the most ancient legislators, thought that the families and the number of citizens ought to remain the same, although originally all the lots may have been of different sizes ; but in 14 the Laws, the opposite principle is maintained. What in our opinion is the right arrangement will have to be explained hereafter ^ . There is another omission in the Laws ; Socrates does not tell us how the rulers differ from their subjects ; he only says that they should be related as the warp and the woof, which 15 are made out of different wools ^. He allows that a man's whole property may be increased fivefold ^, but why should not his land also increase to a certain extent ? Again, will the good management of a household be promoted by his arrange- ment of homesteads ? for he assigns to each individual two 16 homesteads in separate places *, and it is difficult to live in two houses. The whole system of government tends to be neither demo- cracy nor oligarchy, but something in a mean between them, which is usually called a polity, and is composed of the heavy armed soldiers. Now, if he intended to frame a constitution which would suit the greatest number of states, he was very likely right, but not if he meant to say that this constitutional form came nearest to his first or ideal state ; for many would 1 7 prefer the Lacedaemonian, or, possibly, some other more aris- tocratic government. Some, indeed, say that the best consti- ^ Cp. vii. 5. § I ; 10. § II ; 16. § 15 ; bat the promise is hardly fulfilled. * Laws, V. 734 E, 735 A. ^ Laws, v. 744 e. * Laws, V. 745, but cp. infra, vii. to. § il. The Form of Government 71 tution is a combination of all existing forms, and they praise the II.0 Lacedaemonian ^ because it is made up of oligarchy, monarchy, democracy, the king forming the monarchy, and the council of elders the oligarchy, while the democratic element is represented by the Ephors ; for the Ephors are selected from tlie people. Others, however, declare the Ephoralty to be a tyranny, and find the element of democracy in the common meals and in the habits of daily life. In the Law ^, it is " maintained that the best state is made up of democracy and tyranny, which are either not constitutions at all, or are the worst of all. But they are nearer the truth who combine many forms ; for the state is better which is made up of more numerous elements. The constitution proposed in the Laws has no element of monarchy at all ; it is nothing but oligarchy and democracy, leaning rather to oligarchy. This 19 is seen in the mode of appointing magistrates ^ ; for although the appointment of them by lot from among those who have been already selected combines both elements, the way in which the rich are compelled by law to attend the assembly* and vote for magistrates or discharge other political duties, while the rest may do as they like, and the endeavour to have the greater number of the magistrates appointed out of the richest classes and the highest officers selected from those who have the greatest incomes, both these are oligarchical 20 features. The oligarchical principle prevails also in the choice of the council ^ ; for all are compelled to choose, but the compulsion extends only to the choice out of the first 1 Cp. iv. § 7; 7. § 4; 9. §§ 7-9. * vi. 756 e; cp. iv. 710, 3 Laws, vi. 755, 763 E, 765. * Laws, vi. 764 a; and Pol. iv. 9. § 2 ; 14. § 12. ' Laws, vi. 756 B-E. 72 Plato's Laws: II. 6 class, and of an equal number out of the second class and out of the third class, but not in this latter case to all the voters of the third and forth class ; and the selection of candidates out of the fourth class ' is only compulsory on the first and 21 second. Then, he says that there ought to be an equal number of each class selected. Thus a preponderance will ^ be given to the better sort of people, who have the larger incomes, because many of the lower classes, not being cora- 32 pelled, will not vote. These considerations, and others which will be adduced when the time comes for examining similar polities, tend to show that states like Plato's should not be composed of democracy and monarchy. There is also a danger in electing the magistrates out of a body who are themselves elected ; for, if but a small number choose to com- bine, the elections will always go as they desire. Such is the constitution which is described in the Laws. 7 Other constitutions have been proposed ; some by private persons, others by philosophers and statesmen, which all come nearer to established or existing ones than either of Plato's. No one else has introduced such novelties as the community of women and children, or public tables for women : 2 other legislators begin with what is necessary. In the opinion of some, the regulation of property is the chief point ^ of all, that being the question upon which all revolutions turn. This danger was recognized by Phaleas of Chalcedon, who I was the first to affirm that the citizens of a state ought to have 3 equal possessions. He thought that in a new colony the 1266 b equalization might be accomplished without difficulty, not so easily when a state was already established; and that then the shortest way of compassing the desired end would be for ^ Omitting either rod TiTaprov or raiv nrdprojv. Phaleas — Equality of Property 73 j the rich to give and not to leceive marriage portions, and for H, 7 1 the poor not to give but to receive them. Plato in the Laws was of opinion that, to a certain extent, 4 accumulation should be allowed, forbidding, as I have already observed \ any citizen to possess more than five times the minimum qualification. But those who make such laws should 5 remember what they are apt to forget — that the legislator who fixes the amount of property should also fix the number | of children ; for, if the children are too many for the property, the law must be broken. And, besides the violation of the law, it is a bad thing that many from being rich should become poor ; for men of ruined fortunes are sure to stir up revolutions. That the equalization of property exercises an 6 influence on political society was clearly understood even by some of the old legislators. Laws were made by Solon and others prohibiting an individual from possessing as much land as he pleased ; and there are other laws in states which forbid the sale of property : among the Locrians, for example, there is a law that a man is not to sell his property unless he can prove unmistakably that some misfortune has befallen him. 7 Again, there have been laws which enjoin the preservation of the original lots. Such a law existed in the island of Leucas, and the abrogation of it madfe the constitution too democratic, for the rulers no longer had the prescribed qualification. Again, where there is equality of property, the amount may be either too large or too small, and the possessor may be living either in luxury or penury. Clearly, then, the legis-'^ lator ought not only to aim at the equalization of properties, g but at moderation in their amount. And yet, if he prescribe^ this moderate amount equally to all, he will be no nearer the ' c. 6. § 15. 74 Phateasj II. 7 mark ; for it is not the possessions but the desires of mankind ' which require to be equalized \ and this is impossible, unless a sufficient education is provided by the state. But Phaleas will probably reply that this is precisely what he means ; and that, in his opinion, there ought to be in states, not only equal 9 property, but equal education. Still he should tell us what will be the character of his education ; there is no use in having one and the same for all, if it is of a sort that predis- 10 poses men to avarice, or ambition, or both. Moreover, civil troubles arise, not only out of the inequality of property, but * if" ' "* ' jout of the inequality of honour, though in opposite ways. For 1267 althe common people quarrel about the inequality of property, the ♦higher class about the equality of honour ; as the poet says — ' The bad and good alike in honour share '^.' 1 1 There are crimes of which the motive is want ; and for these Phaleas expects to find a cure in the equalization of property, which will take away from a man the temptation to 12 be a highwayman, because he is hungry or cold. But want is not the sole incentive to crime ; men desire to gratify some passion which preys upon them, or they are eager to enjoy the pleasures which are unaccompanied with the pain of desire, and therefore they commit crimes. Now what is the cure of these three disorders ? Of the first, I moderate possessions and occupation ; of the second, habits of temperance ; as to the third, if any desire pleasures which depend on themselves, they will find the satisfaction of their f desires nowhere but in philosophy ; for all other pleasures fg we are dependent on others. The fact is that the greatest V' ,< crimes are caused by excess and not by necessity. Men do 1 Cp. c. 5. § 12 ^ II. ix. 319. His Errors and Omissions yj not become tyiants in order that they may not suffer cold ; II. 7 and hence great is the honour bestowed, not on him who kills a thief, but on him who kills a tyrant. Thus we see that the institutions of Phaleas avail only against petty crimes. There is another objection to them. They are chiefly ^4 designed to promote the internal welfare of the state. But the legislator should consider also its relation to neighbouring nations, and to all who are outside of it \ The government must be organized with a view to military strength ; and of this he has said not a word. And so with respect to pro- 15 peity : there should not only be enough to supply the internal wants of the state, but also to meet dangers coming from without. The property of the state should not be so large that more powerful neighbours may be tempted by it, while the owners are unable to repel the invaders ; nor yet so small that the state is unable to maintain a war even against states of equal power, and of the same character. Phaleas has not 16 laid down any rule ; and we should bear in mind ^ that a cer- tain amount of wealth ^ is an advantage. The best limit will probably be, not so much as will tempt a moVe powerful neigh- bour, or make it his interest to go to war with you. There 17 is a story that Eubulus, when Autophradates was going to besiege Atarneus, told him to consider how long the opera- tion would take, and then reckon up the cost which would be incurred in the time. ' For,' said he, ' I am willing for a smaller sum than that to leave Atarneus at once.' These words of Eubulus made an impression on Autophradates, and he desisted from the siege. One advantage gained by the equalization of property is] that it prevents the citizens from quarrelling. Not that the' * Cp. c. 6. § 7. * Or reading o tl, ' what aaiouiit of wealth.' r 76 Phaleas and Hippodamus J:hey think their due; and this is often found to be a cause „fof sedition and revokition ^ And the avarice of mankind II. 7 g;iin in this direction is very great. For the nobles will be dissatisfied because they do not receive the honours which 1267 bjf is insatiable ; at one time two obols was pay enough, but now, when this sum has become customary, men always want more and more without end ; for it is of the nature of desire not to be satisfied, and most men live only for the gratification of it. ^ The beginning of reform ^ is not so 20 much to equalize property as to train the nobler sort of natures not to desire more, and to prevent the lower from getting more ; that is to say, they must be kept down, but not 21 illtreated. Besides, the equalization proposed by Phaleas is /imperfect; for he only equalizes land, whereas a man may be ' rich also in slaves, and cattle, and money, and in the abun- dance of what are called his movables. Now either all these things must be equalized, or some limit must be imposed on 22 them, or they must all be let alone. It would appear that Phaleas is legislating for a small city only, if, as he supposes, all the artisans are to be public slaves and not to form a part 33 of the population of the city. But if there is a law that artisans are to be public slaves, it should only apply to those engaged on public works ', as at Epidamnus, or at Athens on the plan which Diophantus once introduced. From these observations any one may judge how far Phaleas was wrong or right in his ideas. 8 Hippodamus, the son of Euryphon, a native of Miletus, the 1 Cp. § lo. * Or, reading with Beniays d'/f?;, ' the remedy for such evils.' 3 Putting a comma after thai and removing the comma after Hippodamus — His Constitution and Laws 77 same who invented the art of planning cities, and who also II. 8 laid out the Piraeus — a strange man, whose fondness for dis- tinction led him into a general eccentricity of life, which made some think him affected (for he would wear flowing hair and expensive ornaments ; and yet he dressed himself in the same cheap warm garment both in winter and summer) ; he, besides aspiring to be an adept in the knowledge of nature, was the first person not a statesman who made enquiries about the best form of government. The city of Hippodamus was composed of io,ooo citizens 2 divided into tliree parts — one of artisans, one of husbandmen, and a third of armed defenders of the state. He also divided 3 the land into three parts, one sacred, one public, the third private : the first was set apart to maintain the customary worship of the gods, the second was to support the warriors, the third was the property of the husbandmen. He also 4 ■ divided his laws into three classes, and no more, for he main- tained that there are three subjects of lawsuits — Insult, | injury, and homicide. He likewise instituted a single final >• court of appeal, to which all causes seeming to have been improperly decided might be referred ; this court he formed of elders chosen for the purpose. He was further of opinion I'^f'? a that the decisions of the courts ought not to be given by the 5 use of a voting pebble, but that every one should have a tablet on which he might not only write a simple condemnation, or leave the tablet blank for a simple acquittal ; but, if he partly acquitted and partly condemned, he was to distinguish accord- ingly. To the existing law he objected that it obliged the judges to be guilty of perjury, whichever way they voted. He also enacted that those who discovered anything for th&-6— Rf^fUfU 3^ good of the state should be rewarded ; and he provided that 7 8 Hippodamus — His Confusions II. 8 the children of citizens who died in battle should be main- jctained at the public expense, as if such an enactment had never been heard of before, yet it actually exists at Athens ^ 1 and in other places. As to the magistrates, he would have )them all elected by the people, that is, by the three classes 'already mentioned, and those who were elected were to watch over the interests of the public, of strangers and of orphans. These are the most striking points in the constitution of Hippodamus. There is not much else. The first of these proposals to which objection may be 8 taken, is the threefold division of the citizens. The artisans, and the husbandmen, and the warriors, all have a share in the government. But the husbandmen have no arms, and the ' artisans neither arms nor land, and therefore they become all 9 but slaves of the warrior class. That they should share in all the offices is an impossibility ; for generals and guardians of the citizens, and nearly all the principal magistrates, must be taken from the class of those who carry arms. Yet, if the two other classes have no share in the government, how can they be loyal citizens ? It may be said that those who have arms must necessarily be masters of both the other classes, but this is not so easily accomplished unless they are numer- ic ous ; and if they are, wliy should the other classes share in the government at all, or have power to appoint magistrates ? Artisans there must be, for these are wanted in every city, and they can live by their craft, as elsewhere ; and the hus- bandmen, too, if they really provided the warriors with food, might fairly have a share in the government. But in the republic of Hippodamus they are supposed to have land of their own, which they cultivate for their private benefit. ^ Cp. Thuc. ii. c. 46. Courts of haw: Inventions 79 Again, as to this common land out of which the soldiers are II. 8 maintained, if they are themselves to be the cultivators of it, n the warrior class will be identical with the husbandmen, although the legislator intended to make a distinction between them. If, again, there aie to be other cultivators distinct both from the husbandmen, who have land of their own, and from the warriors, they will make a fourth class, which has no place in the state and no share in anything. Or, if the k same persons are to cultivate their own lands and those of the public as well, they will have a difficulty in supplying the quantity of produce which will maintain two households : and 1268 b why, in this case, should there be any division, for they might find food themselves and give to the warriors from the same lots ? There is surely a great confusion in all this. Neither is the law to be commended which says that the 13 judges, when a simple issue is laid before them, should dis- tinguish in their judgment ; for the judge is thus converted into an arbitrator. Now, in an arbitration, although the arbitrators are many, they confer with one another about the decision, and therefore they can distinguish ; but in courts of lav\^ this is impossible, and, indeed, most legislators take pains to prevent the judges from holding any communication with one another. Again, will there not be confusion if the judge 14 thinks that damages should be given, but not so much as the suitor demands ? He asks, say, for twenty minae, and the judge allows him ten minae, or one judge more and another less ; one five, another four minae. In this way they will go on apportioning the damages, and some will grant the whole and others nothing: how is the final reckoning to be taken ? 15 Again, no one who votes for a simple acquittal or condemna- tion is compelled to perjure himself, if the indictment is quite tAtf^ ^[t 80 Should Laws be Changed. II. 8 simple and in right form ; for the judge who acquits does not decide that the defendant owes nothing, but that he does not owe the twenty minae. He only is guilty of perjury who thinks that the defendant ought not to pay twenty minae, and yet condemns him. 16 To reward those who discover anything which is useful to \the state is a proposal which has a specious sound, but cannot safely be enacted by law, for it may encourage informers, and perhaps even lead to political commotions. This question involves another. It has been doubted whether it is or is not expedient to make any changes in the laws of a country, even 17 if another law be better. Now, if all changes are inexpedient, we can hardly assent to the proposal of Hippodamus ; for, under pretence of doing a public service, a man may introduce measures which are really destructive to the laws or to the constitution. But, since we have touched upon this subject, 18 perhaps we had better go a little into detail, for, as I was saying, there is a difference of opinion, and it may sometimes seem desirable to make changes. Such changes in the other arts and sciences have certainly been beneficial ; medicine, for example, and gymnastic, and every other art and science have departed from traditional usage. And, if politics be an art, 19 change must be necessary in this as in any other art. The need of improvement is shown by the fact that old customs are exceedingly simple and barbarous. For the ancient Hellenes went about armed ^ and bought their wives of each 20 other. The remains of ancient laws which have come down 1269 a to us are quite absurd ; for example, at Cumae there is a law about murder, to the effect that if the accuser produce a certain number of witnesses from among liis own kinsmen, the accused ' Cp. Thucyd, i. c. 5 and 6. should Laws be Changed ^ 8 1 shall be held guilty. Again, men in general desire the good, II. 8 and not merely what their fathers had. But the primaeval 21 inhabitants \ whether they were born of the earth, or were the survivors of some destruction, may be supposed to have been no better than ordinary foolish people among ourselves ^ (such is certainly the tradition^ concerning the earth-born men) ; and it would be ridiculous to rest contented with their notions. Even when laws have been written down, they ought not always to remain unaltered. As in other arts, so inj2 2 making a constitution, it is impossible that all things should bel precisely set down in writing; for enactments must be uni-| versal, but actions are concerned with particulars '. Hence \v^ infer that sometimes and in certain cases laws may be changed ; but when we look at the matter from another point of view, great caution would seem to be required. For the habit of 23 lightly changing the laws is an evil, and, when the advantage is small, some errors both of lawgivers and rulers had better be left ; the citizen will not gain so much by the change as he 1 will lose by the habit of disobedience. The analogy of the I24 arts is false ; a change in a law is a very different thing from a change in an art. For the law has no power to command obedience except that of habit, which can only be given by time, so that a readiness to change from old to new laws enfeebles the power of the law. Even if we admit that the 25 laws are to be changed, are they all to be changed, and in every state ? And are they to be changed by anybody who ^ Or, referring o/xoi'oi;? to "^rf^ivth, ' whether they were born of the earth cr were the survivors of some destruction, who were no better {yiJLoiovs) than eirth-born men, may be supposed to have been ordinary foolish people.' ^ Cp. Pkto, Laws, iii. 677 a; Polit. 271 A; Tim. 22 c. 3 Cp. Plaio, Pulit. 295 A. DAVIS G 8 2 Sparta: the Helots; II. 8 likes, or only by certain persons ? These ai'e very important questions ; and therefore we had better reserve the discussion of them to a more suitable occasion. 9 In the governments of Lacedaemon and Crete, and indeed in all governments, two points have to be considered ; first, whether any particular law is good or bad, when compared with the perfect state ; secondly, whether it is or is not con- sistent with the idea and character which the lawgiver has set 2 before his citizens ^. That in a well-ordered state the citizens should have leisure and not have to provide for their daily wants is generally acknowledged, but there is a difficulty in seeing how this leisure is to be attained. [For, if you employ • slaves, they are liable to rebel.] The Thessalian Penestae have often risen against their masters, and the Helots in like manner against the Lacedaemonians, for whose misfortunes 3 they are always lying in wait. Nothing, however, of this 1269 b ]iJnd has as yet happened to the Cretans ; the reason probably is that the neighbouring cities, even when at war with one I another, never form an alliance with rebellious serfs, rebellions not being for their interest, since they themselves have a de- pendent population ". Whereas all the neighbours of the Lacedaemonians, whether Argives, Messenians, or Arcadians, are their enemies [and the Helots are always revolting to them]. In Thessaly, again, the original revolt of the slaves occurred at a time when the Thessalians were still at war with the neighbouring Achaeans, Perrhaebians, and Magnesians. 4 Besides, if there were no other difficulty, the treatment or management of slaves is a troublesome affair ; for, if not kept in hand, they are insolent, and think that they are as good as their masters, and, if harshly treated, they hate and conspire 1 Or 'himself (Bernajs). ^ Cp. c. lo. § 5. Licence of the Women 8 3 against them. Now it is clear that when these are the re- II. suits the citizens of a state have not found out the secret of managing their subject population. Again, the licence of the Lacedaemonian women defeats 5 the intention of the Spartan constitution, and is adverse to the good order of the state. For a husband and a wife, being each a part of every family, the state may be considered as about equally divided into men and women ; and, therefore, in those states in which the condition of the women is bad, half! the city^ may be regarded as having no laws. And this isle what has actually happened at Sparta ; the legislator wanted to make the whole state hardy and temperate, and he has carried out his intention in the case of the men, but he has neglected the women, who live in every sort of intemperance and luxury. ->t The consequence is that in such a state wealth is too highly 7 valued, especially if the citizens fall under the dominion of their wives, after the manner of all warlike races, except the . Celts and a few others who openly approve of male loves. \ The old mythologer would seem to have been right in uniting 8 Ares and Aphrodite, for all warlike races are prone to the love either of men or of women. This was exemplified among the Spartans in the days of their greatness ; many things were managed by their women. But what difference does it make 9 whether women rule, or the rulers are ruled by women ? The result is the same. Even in regard to courage, which is of no use in daily life, and is needed only in war, the influence of the Lacedaemonian women has been most mischievous. The 10 evil showed itself in the Theban invasion, when, unlike the women in other cities, they were utterly useless and caused more confusion than the enemy. This licence of the Lacedae- 1 Cp. i. 13. § 16. G 2 84 Sparta: Inequality of Property ^ II. 9 monian women existed fiom the earliest times, and was only 1270 a what might be expected. For, during the wars of the Lace- daemonians, first against the Argives, and afterwards against the Arcadians and Messenians, the men were long away from home, and, on the return of peace, they gave themselves into the legislator's hand, already prepared by the discipline of ■ a soldier's life (in wliich there are many elements of virtue\ to receive his enactments. But, when Lycurgus, as tradition says, wanted to bi-ing the women under his laws, they resisted, 12 and he gave up the attempt. They, and not he, are to blame for what then happened, and this defect in the constitution is clearly to be attributed to them. We are not, however, con- sidering what is or is not to be excused, but what is right or 13 wrong ; and the disorder of the women, as I have already said, not only of itself gives an air of indecorum to the state, but tends in a measure to foster avarice. The mention of avarice naturally suggests a criticism on the 14 inequality of property. While some of the Spartan citizens » have quite small properties, others have very large ones ; hence i the land has passed into the hands of a few. And here is another fault in their laws ; for, although the legislator rightly holds up to shame the sale or purchase of an inheritance, he T% allows anybody who likes to give and bequeath it. Yet both practices lead to the same result. And nearly two-fifths of the whole country are held by women ; this is owing to the number of heiresses and to the large dowries which are cus- tomary. It would surely have been better to have given no dowries at all, or, if any, but small or moderate ones. As the law now stands, a man may bestow his heiress on any one Iwhom he pleases, and, if he die intestate, the jirivilege of i6|giving her away descends to his heir. Hence, although the Criticism of the Ephoralty Sy country is able to maintain 1500 cavalry and 30,000 hoplites, II. 9 the whole number of Spartan citizens [at the time of the Theban invasion] fell below 1000. The result proves the faulty nature of their laws respecting property ; for the city sank under a single defeat ; the want of men was their ruin. There is a tradition that, in the days of their ancient kings, 17 they were in the habit of giving the rights of citizenship to strangers, and theiefore, in spite of their long wars, no lack of population was experienced by them ; indeed, at one time Sparta is said to have numbered not less than 10,000 citizens. Whether this statement is true or not, it would certainly have been better to have maintained their numbers by the equalizaf tion of property. Again, the law which relates to the pro- 18 creation of children is adverse to the correction of this inequality. For the legislator, wanting to have as many 1270 b Spartans as he could, encouraged the citizens to have large families ; and there is a law at Sparta that the father of three sons shall be exempt from military service, and he who has- , four from all the burdens of the state. Yet it is obvious that, i^ if there were many children, the land being distributed as it is, many of them must necessarily fall into poverty. The Lacedaemonian constitution is defective in another /• point ; I mean the Ephoralty. This magistracy has authority in the highest matters, but the Ephors are all chosen from the people, and so the office is apt to fall into the hands of very i poor men, who, being badly off, are open to bribes. There ^o have been many examples at Sparta of this evil in former ^frlv times; and quite recently, in the matter of the Andrians, certain of the Ephors who were bribed did their best to ruin the state. And so great and tyrannical is their power, that even the kings have been compelled to court them ; through \n 8 6 Sparta : Criticism of the Coiuuil of Elders ; II. 9 their influence the constitution has deteriorated, and from 21 being an aristocracy has turned into a democracy. The vEphoralty certainly does keep the state together; for the people are contented when they have a share in the highest office, and the result, whether due to the legislator or to 22 chance, has been advantageous. For if a constitution is to be permanent, all the parts of the state must wish that it should exist and be maintained^. This is the case at Sparta, where the kings desire permanence because they have due honour in their own persons ; the nobles are represented in the council of elders (for the office of elder is a reward of virtue) ; and 23 the people in the Ephoralty, for all are eligible to it. The I election of Ephors out of the whole people is perfectly right, but ought not to be carried on in the present fashion, which is too childish. Again, they have the decision of great causes, although they are quite ordinary men, and therefore they should not determine them merely on their own judgment, but accord- 24 ing to written rules, and to the laws. Their way of life, too, is not in accordance with the spirit of the constitution — they have a deal too much licence ; whereas, in the case of the other citizens, the excess of strictness is so intolerable that they run away from the law into the secret indulgence of sensual pleasures. 25 Again, the council of elders is not free from defects. It may be said that the elders are good men and well trained in manly virtue ; and that, therefore, there is an advantage to the state in having them. But that judges of important causes X should hold office for life is not a good thing, for the mind 1271 a grows old as well as the body. And when men have been educated in such a manner that even the legislator himself 1 Cp. iv. 9. § 10; V. 9. § 5, Further Criticisms 87 cannot trust them, there is real danger. Many of the elders II. 9 are well known to have taken bribes and to have been guilty of ^6 partiality in public affairs. And therefore they ought not to be irresponsible ; yet at Sparta they are so. But (it may be replied), ' All magistracies are accountable to the Ephors.' ^ Yes, but this prerogative is too great for them, and we main- tain that the control should be exercised in some other manner. Further, the mode in which the Spartans elect their elders is 27 childish ; and it is improper that ^ the person to be elected I should canvass for the office ; the worthiest should be ap- pointed, whether he chooses or not. And here the legislator 28 clearly indicates the same intention which appears in other parts of his constitution ; he would have his citizens ambitious, and he has reckoned upon this quality in the election of the elders ; for no one would ask to be elected if he were not. Yet ambition and avarice, almost more than any other passions, \ are the motives of crime. Whether kings are or are not an advantage to states, I will 29 consider at another time "^ ; they should at any rate be chosen, not as they are now, but with regard to their personal life and | conduct. The legislator himself obviously did not suppose 3° that he could make them really good men ; at least he shows a great distrust of their virtue. For this reason the Spartans used to join enemies in the same embassy, and the quarrels between the kings were held to be conservative of the state. Neither did the first introducer of the common meals, called nr, 'phiditia,' regulate them well. The entertainment ought to 31 have been provided at the public cost, as in Crete ^; but ^ Reading to avrov, not tw, as Bekker, 2nd edit., apparen'.ly Dy a misprint. « Cp. iii. 14 foil. ' Cp. c. 10. §§ 7, S. $. 8 8 Sparta: Further Criticisms II. 9 among the Lacedaemonians every one is expected to contri- l bute, and some of them are too poor to afford the expense ; 32 thus the intention of the legislator is frustrated. The common meals were meant to be a popular institution, but the existing manner of regulating them is the reverse of popular. For the very poor can scarcely take part in them ; and, according to ancient custom, those who cannot contribute are not allowed to retain their rights of citizenship. 33 The law about the Spaitan admirals has often been censured, and with justice ; it is a source of dissension, for tlie kings are perpetual generals ^, and this office of admiral is but the setting up of another king. 1271 b The charge which Plato brings, in the Laws ^, against the ^'^ in_tention of the legislator, is likewise justified; the whole con- stitution has regard to one part of virtue only — the virtue of the soldier, which gives victory in war. And so long as they were at war, their power was preserved, but when they had attained empire they fell ', for of the arts of peace they knew nothing, and had never engaged in any employment higher 35 than war. There is another error, equally great, into which they have fallen. Although they truly think that the goods for which they contend are to be acquired by virtue rather than by vice, they err in supposing that these goods are to be pre- ferred to the virtue which gains them. .-. 3^ Once more : J;he revenues of the state are ill-managed ; ' * there is no money in the treasuiy, although they are obliged to carry on great wars, and they are unwilling to pay taxes. The greater part of the land being in the hands of tlie Spar- tans, they do not look closely into one another's contributions. * Reading aibioi';. ^ Laws, i. C30. * Cp. vii. 14. § 2 2. Sparta and Crete 89 The result which the legislator has produced is the reverse of II. 9 beneficial ; for he has made his city poor, and his citizens 37 greedy. Enough respecting the Spartan constitution, of which these are the principal defects. jrhe_xaas,Utytion5..Qf „the^^Clgi^ cities nearly resemble the 10 Spartan, and in some few points are quite as good ; but for the most part less perfect in form. The older constitutions are generally less elaborate than the later, and the Lacedaemonian is said to be, and probably is, in a very great measure, a copy 2 of those in Crete. According to tradition, Lycurgus, when he ceased to be the guardian of King Charilaus, went abroad and spent a long time in Crete. For the two countries are nearly connected ; the Lyctians are a colony of the Lacedae- monians, and the colonists, when they came to Crete, adopted the constitution which they found existing among the inhabi- 3 tants. Even to this day the Perioeci, or subject population of Crete, are governed by the original laws which Minos enacted. The island seems to be intended by nature for dominion in Hellas, and to be well situated ; it extends right across the sea, around which nearly all the Hellenes are settled ; and while one end is not far from the Peloponnese, the other almost reaches to the region of Asia about Triopium and 4 Rhodes. Hence Minos acquired the empire of the sea, sub- duing some of the islands and colonizing others ; at last he invaded Sicily, where he died near Camicus. 5 The Cretan institutions resemble the Lacedaemonian. The / , Helots are the husbandmen of the one, the Perioeci of the 1272 a other, and both Cretans and Lacedaemonians have common meals, which were anciently called by the Lacedaemonians not * phiditia ' but ' andria ' ; and the Cretans have the same word, 90 Crete and Sparta II. 10 the use of which proves that tlie common meals [or syssitia] 6 originally came from Crete. Further, the two constitutions are similar [in many particulars] ; for the office of the Ephors is the same as that of the Cretan Cosmi, the only difference being that whereas the Ephors are five, the Cosmi are ten in number. The elders, too, answer to the elders in Crete, who are termed by the Cretans the council. And the kingly office once existed in Crete, but was abolished, and the Cosmi have ^ now the duty of leading them in war. All classes share in the ecclesia, but it can only ratify the decrees of the elders and the Cosmi. Ji 2- V The common meals of Crete are certainly better managed than the Lacedaemonian ; for in Lacedaemon every one pays so much per head, or, if he fails, the law, as I have already explained, forbids him to exercise the rights of citizenship. 8 But in Crete they are of a more popular character. There, of all the fruits of the earth, of cattle, of the public revenues, and of the tribute which is paid by the Perioeci, one portion is Assigned to the gods and to the service of the state, and 'another to the common meals, so that men, women, and 9 children are all supported out of a common stock ^. The legislator has many ingenious ways of securing moderation in eating which he conceives to be a gain ; he likewise encourages the separation of men from women, lest they should have too many children, and the companionship of men with one another I — whether this is a good or bad thing I shall have an oppor- tunity of considering at another time ''■. But that the Cretan common meals are better ordered than the Lacedaemonian there can be no doubt. On the other hand, the Cosmi are even a worse institution \ ■^ < 1 Cp. vii. 10. § 10. 2 vii. i6 (?). Cretan Cosmi and Elders 9 i than the Ephors, of which they have all the evils without the II. 10 good. Like the Ephors, they are any chance persons, but in ^° Crete this is not counterbalanced by a corresponding political advantage. At Sparta every one Is eligible, and the body of the people, having a share in the highest office, want the state to be permanent ^. But in Crete the Cosmi are elected out of certain families, and not out of the whole people, and the elders out of those who have been Cosmi. The same criticism may be made about the Cretan, which 1 1 has been already made about the Lacedaemonian elders. Their irresponsibility and life tenure is too great a privilege, and their arbitrary power of acting upon their own judgment, and dispensing with written law, is dangerous. It is no proof 12 of the goodness of the institution that the people are not discontented at being excluded from it. For there is no profit to be made out of the office ; and, unlike the Ephors, 1272 b the Cosmi, being In an Island, are removed from temptation. The remedy by which they correct the evil of this institu- 13 tion is an extraordinary one, suited rather to a close oligarchy than to a constitutional state. For the Cosmi are often ex- pelled by a conspiracy of their own colleagues, or of private irdivlduals ; and they are allowed also to resign before their term of office has expired. Surely all matters of this kind are better regulated by law than by the will of man, which Is a very unsafe rule. Worst of all Is the suspension of the.14 office of Cosmi, a device to which the nobles often have! recourse when they will not submit to justice. This shows that the Cretan government, although possessing some of the characteristics of a constitutional state, is really a close oligarchy. ^ Cp. supra, c. 9. § 21. 9 2 Carthage: Merits and II. 10 The Cretans have a habit, too, of setting up a chief; they get together a party among the common people and gather their friends and then quarrel and fight with one another. 15 What is this but the temporary destruction of the state and dissokition of society ? A city is in a dangerous condition when those who are willing are also able to attack her. But, as I have already said, the island of Crete is saved by her situation ; distance has the same effect as the Lacedaemonian 16 prohibition of strangers ; and the Cretans have no foreign dominions. This is the reason why the Perioeci are contented in Crete, whereas the Helots are perpetually revolting. But when lately foreign invaders found their way into the island, the weakness of the Cretan constitution was revealed. Enough of the government of Crete. 11 The Cartliaainians are also considered to liave an excellent form of government, which differs from that of any other state in several respects, though it is in some very like the Lacedaemonian. Indeed, all three states — the Lacedaemonian, the Cretan, and the Carthaginian — nearly resemble one another, and are very different from any others. Many of the Cartha- 2 ginian institutions are excellent. The superiority of their constitution is proved by the fact that, although containing an element of democracy, it has been lasting ; the Carthaginians have never had any rebellion worth speaking of, and have never been under the rule of a tyrant. 3 Among the points in which the Carthaginian constitution resembles the Lacedaemonian are the following:— The com- mon tables of the clubs answer to the Spartan phiditia, and their magistracy of the 104 to the Ephors ; but, whereas the Ephors are any chance persons, the magistrates of the Cartha- ginians are elected according to merit — this is an improvement. Defects of the Constitution 93 They have also their kings and their gerusia, or council of II. 11 elders, who correspond to the kings and elders of Sparta. Their kings, unlike the Spartan, are not always of the samej4 family, and this an ordinary one, but if there is some dis-1 tinguished family they are selected out of it and not appointed ' by seniority— this is far better. Such officers have great power, and therefore, if they are persons of little worth, do a great deal of harm, and they have already done harm at 1273 a Lacedaemon. Most of the defects or deviations from the perfect state, for 5 which the Carthaginian constitution would be censured, apply t. r, ^^ equally to all the forms of government which we have men- ^ 5(vf" tioned. But of the deflections from aristocracy and constitu. tional government, some incline more to democracy and some to oligarchy. The kings and elders, if unanimous, may determine whether they will or will not bring a matter before the people, but when they are not unanimous, the people may decide whether or not the matter shall be brought forward. And 6 whatever the kings and elders bring before the people is not 1 only heard but also determined by them, and any one who likes ! may oppose it ; now this is not permitted in Sparta and Crete. That the magistracies of five who have under them many 7 important matters should be co-opted, that they should choose the supreme council of 100, and should hold office longer than other magistrates (for they are virtually rulers both before and after they hold office) — these are oligarchical features ; their being without salary and not elected by lot, and any similar points, such as the practice of having all suits tried by the magistrates-^, and not some by one class of judges or jurors and some by another, as at Lacedaemon, are characteristic of ' Cp. iii. I. §§ 10, II ; and see note at end. 94 Carthage a Plutocracy : II. 11 aristocracy. The Carthaginian constitution deviates from ° aristocracy and inclines to oligarchy, chiefly on a point where popular opinion is on their side. For men in general think that magistrates should be chosen not only for their merit, but for their wealth : a man, they say, who is poor cannot rule well 9 — he has not the leisure. If, then, election of magistrates for their wealth be characteristic of oligarchy, and election for merit of aristocracy, there will be a third form under which the constitution of Carthage is comprehended ; for the Cartha- ginians choose their magistrates, and particularly the highest of them — their kings and generals — with an eye both to merit ■and to wealth. lo" But we must acknowledge that, in thus deviating from aristocracy, the legislator has committed an error. Nothing is more absolutely necessary than to provide that the highest class, not only when in office, but when out of office, should have leisure and not demean themselves in any way ; and to this his atten- tion should be first directed. Even if you must have regard to wealth, in order to secure leisure, yet it is surely a bad thing I that the greatest offices, such as those of kings and generals, if should be bought. The law which allows this abuse makes wealth of more account than virtue, and the whole state becomes avaricious. For, whenever the chiefs of the state deem anything honourable, the other citizens are sure to follow 1273 b their example ; and, where virtue has not the first place, there 12 aristocracy cannot be firmly established. Those who have been at the expense of purchasing their places will be in the ^ habit of repaying themselves ; and it is absurd to suppose that a poor and honest man will be wanting to make gains, and that a lower stamp of man who has incurred a great expense will not. Wherefore they should rule who are able to "ule best Preserved by Accident 95" \api For, as I was saying, this arrangement is more popular, and any action familiarized by repetition is better and sooner per- formed. We have a proof in military and naval matters ; the duties of command and of obedience in both these services extend to all. The government of the Carthaginians is oligarchical, but 15 they successfully escape the evils of oligarchy by their wealth, which enables them from time to time to send out some portion of the people' to their colonies. This is their panacea and the means by which they give stability to the state. Accident favours them, but the legislator should be . able to provide against revolution without trusting to accidents. As things are, if any misfortune occurred, and the people 16 revolted from their rulers, there would be no way of restoring peace by legal methods. 1 Cp. c. 9. § 2. * Cp. Plato, Rep. ii. 374 a. * Or, removing the comma after itXovTuv, and adding one after fjiepos, ' by enriching one portion of the people after another whom they send to their colonies.' Cp. vi. 5. § 9, which tends to confirm this way of taking the words. ^6 Solo?} and the Athenian Constitution II. 11 Such is the character of the Lacedaemonian, Cretan, and Carthaginian constitutions, which are justly celebrated. 12 Of those who have treated of governments, some have never taken any part at all in public affairs, but have passed their lives in a private station ; about most of them, what was worth telling has been already told. Others have been law- givers, either in their own or in foreign cities, whose affairs they have administered ; and of these some have only made laws, others have framed constitutions ; for example, Lycurgus 2 and Solon did both. Of the Lacedaemonian constitution I have already spoken. As to Solon, he is thought by some to have been a good legislator, who put an end to the ex- clusiveness of the oligarchy, emancipated the people, established the ancient Athenian democracy, and harmonized the different elements of the state. According to their view, the council of Areopagus was an oligarchical element, the elected magis- 1274 a tracy, aristocratical, and the courts of law, democratical. The truth seems to be that the council and the elected magistracy 5- existed before the time of Solon, and were retained by him, but that he formed the courts of law out of all the citizens, ,_thus creating the democracy, which is the very reason why he is sometimes blamed. For in giving the supreme power to the law courts, which are elected by lot, he is thought to have 4 destroyed the non-democratic element. When the law courts grew powerful, to please the people, who were now playing the tyrant, the old constitution was changed into the existing democracy. _E£hialtes and^Pencks curtailed the power of the X Areopagus ; they also instituted the payment of the juries, and thus eveiy demagogue in turn increased the power of the 6 democracy until it became what we now see. All this is true; it seems however to be the result of circumstances, and not to Famous Lawgivers 97 have been intended by Solon. For the people having been II. 12 instrumental in gaining the empire of the sea in the Persian War ^, began to get a notion of itself, and followed worthless demagogues, whom the better class opposed. Solon himself appears to have given the Athenians only that power of electing to offices and calling to account the magistrates, which was absolutely necessary^; for without it they would have been in a state of slavery and enmity to the government. All the 6 magistrates he appointed from the notables and the men of wealth, that is to say, from the pentacosio-medimni, or from the class called zeugitae (because they kept a yoke of oxen), or from a third class of so-called knights or cavalry. The fourth class were labourers who had no share in any magistracy. Mere legislators were Zaleucus, who gave laws to the Epi- zephyrian, Locrians, and Charondas, who legislated for his own city of Catana, and for the other Chalcidian cities in Italy and Sicily. Some persons attempt ^ to make out that 7 Onomacritus was the first person who had any special skill in legislation*, and that he, although a Locrian by birth, was trained in Crete, where he lived in the exercise of his prophetic art ; that Thales was his companion, and that Lycurgus and Zaleucus were disciples of Thales, as Charondas was of Zaleucus. But their account is quite inconsistent with 8 chronology. There was also a Theban legislator, whose name was Philolaus, the Corinthian. This Philolaus was one of the family of the Bacchiadae, and a lover of Diodes, the Olympic victor, who left Corinth in horror of the incestuous passion * Cp. V. 4. § 8; viii. 6. § 11. ^ Cp. iii. il. § 8. ' Or (with Bernays), ' to make out an unbroken series of great legis- lators, Onomacritus being considered the first.' DAVIS H o8 Famous Lawgivers II. 12 which his mother Halcyone had conceived for him, and retired to Thebes, where the two friends together ended their days. 9 The inhabitants still point out their tombs, which are in full view of one another, but one looks towards Corinth, the other not. Tradition says that the two friends arranged them in this way. Diodes out of horror at his misfortunes, so that the land of Corinth might not be visible from his tomb ; Philolaus 1274 b that it might. This is the reason why they settled at Thebes, ^° and so Philolaus legislated for the Thebans, and, besides some other enactments, gave them laws about the procreation of children, which they call the ' Laws of Adoption.' These laws were peculiar to him, and were intended to preserve the number of the lots. 11 In the legislation of Charondas there is nothing remarkable, except the laws about false witnesses. He is the first who instituted actions for perjury. His laws are more exact and more precisely expressed than even those of our modern legislators. 12 Characteristic of Phaleas is the equalization of property; of Plato, the community of women, children, and property, the common meals of women, and the law about drinking, that the sober shall be masters of the feast ^ ; also the training of soldiers to acquire by practice equal skill with both hands, so that one should be as useful as the other ''■. 13 Draco has left laws, but he adapted them to a constitution which already existed, and there is no peculiarity in them which is worth mentioning, except the greatness and severity of the punishments. Pittacus, too, was only a lawgiver, and not the author of a constitution ; he has a law which is peculiar to him, that, if * Cp. Laws, ii. 671 D-672 a. * Cp. Laws, vii. 794 D. Famous Lawgivers 99 a drunken man strike another, he shall be more heavily II, 12 punished than if he were sober ^ ; he looked not to the excuse ^ which might be offered for the drunkard, but only to expedi- ency, for drunken more often than sober people commit acts of violence. Androdamas of Rhegium gave laws to the Chalcidians of i^ Thrace. Some of them relate to homicide, and to heiresses ; but there is nothing remarkable in them. And here let us conclude our enquiry into the various con- stitutions which either actually exist, or have been devised by theorists. > Cp. N. Eth. iii. 5. § 8. H 2 BOOK III Qik) III. 1 He who would enquire into the nature and various kinds of government must first of all determine ' What is a state ? ' At present this is a disputed question. Some say that the state has done a certain act ; others, no, not the state \ but the oligarchy or the tyrant. And the legislator or statesman is concerned entirely with the state ; a constitution or government being an ^f ft 2 arrangement of the inhabitants of a state. But a state is com- ■ posite, and, like any other whole, made up of many parts ; — I these are the citizens, .who compose it. It is evident, there- 1275 a fore, that we must begin by asking, Who is the citizen, and what is the meaning of the term ? For here again there may be a difference of opinion. He who is a citizen in a demo- 3 cracy will often not be a citizen in an oligarchy. Leaving out of consideration those who have been made citizens, or who have obtained the name of citizen in any other accidental I manner, we may say, first, that a citizen is not a citizen l^arytijif <* ^hl • 4 because he lives in a certain place, for resident aliens and //v JJ^^f • ' slaves share in the place ; nor is he a citizen who has no legal right except that of suing and being sued ; for this right may be enjoyed under the provisions of a treaty. Even resident aliens in many places possess such rights, although in an ' imperfect f(>rm ; for they are obliged to have a patron. 5 Hence they do but imperfectly participate in citizenship, and we call them citizens only in a qualified sense, as we might apply the term to children who are too young to be on the ' Cp. c. 3. § I. T^he Definition of Citi-x^nship in Theoiy loi register, or to old men who have been relieved from state III. 1 duties. Of these we do not say simply that they are citizens, but add in the one case that they are not of age, and in the other, that they are past the age, or something of that sort ; the precise expression is immaterial, for our meaning is clear. Similar difficulties to those which I have mentioned may be raised and answered about deprived citizens and about exiles. ■< But the citizen, whom we are seeking to define, is a citizen in . the strictest sense, against whom no such exception can be \ taken, and his special characteristic is that he shares in the |, administration of justice, and in offices. Now of offices some & have a limit of time, and the same persons are not allowed to hold them twice, or can only hold them after a fixed interval ; others have no limit of time — for example, the office of dicast or ecclesiast ^. It may, indeed, be argued that these are not ^ magistrates at all, and that their functions give them no share in the government. But surely it is ridiculous to say that those who have the supreme power do not govern. Not to dwell further upon this, which is a purely verbal question, what we want is a common term including both dicast and ecclesiast. Let us, for the sake of distinction, call it 'inde-. terminate office,' and we will assume that those who share in I such office are citizens. This is the most comprehensive (8 definition of a citizen, and best suits all those who are generally so called. But we must not forget that things of which the underlying notions differ in kind, one of them being first, another second, another third, have, when regarded in this relation, nothing, or hardly anything, worth mentioning in common. Now we 9 ^ ' Dicast '= juryman and judge in one: ' ecclesiast ' = member of the ecclesia or assembly of the citizens. I02 77;*? Defitiition of Citi':^7ishtp in Practice III, 1 see that governments differ in kind, and that some of them 1275 b are prior and that others are posterior ; those which are faulty or perverted are necessarily posterior to those which are perfect. (What we mean by perversion will be hereafter explained ^.) The citizen then of necessity differs under each 10 form of government ; and our definition is best adapted to the citizen of a democracy ; but not necessarily to other states. For in some states the people are not acknowledged, nor have they any regular assembly, but only extraordinary ones ; and suits are distiibuted in turn among the magistrates. At Lace- daemon, for instance, the Ephors determine suits about con- tracts, which they distribute among themselves, while the elders are judges of homicide, and other causes are decided 11 by other magistrates. A similar principle prevails at Car- thage ^ ; there certain magistrates decide all causes. We may, indeed, modify our definition of the citizen so as to include these states. [But strictly taken it only applies in democracies.] I In other states it is the holder of a determinate, not of an lindeterniiflate, office who legislates and judges, and to sorne I or all such holders of determinate offices is reserved the right of deliberating or judging about some things or about all 32 things. The conception of the citizen now begins to clear up. g He who has the power to take part in the deliberative or ^judicial administration of any state is said by us to be a citizen l^f that state ; and speaking generally, a state is a body of citizens sufficing for the purposes of life. 2 But in practice a citizen is defined to be one of whom both X the parents are citizens ; others insist on going further back ; ^' say to two or three or more grandparents. This is a short and practical definition ; but there are some who raise the > Cp. c. 6. § II. " Cp. ii. II. § 7. Difficulties Created by l{evolutions 103 further question : How this third or fourth ancestor came to III. 2 be a citizen ? Gorgias of Leontini, partly because he was in a difficulty, partly in irony, said — 'Mortars are made by the mortar-makers, and the citizens of Larissa are also a manu- factured article, made, like the kettles which bear their name \Kap\.(rcu.oi\^ by the magistrates ^' Yet the question is really 3 simple, for if, according -to the definition just given, they shared in the government^, they were citizens. [This is a better definition than the other.] For the words, 'born of a father or mother, who is a citizen,' cannot possibly apply to the first inhabitants or founders of a state. There is a greater difficulty in tlie case of those who have been made citizens after a revolution, as by Cleisthenes at Athens after the expulsion of the tyrants, for he enrolled in tribes a number of strangers and slaves and^ resident aliens. The doubt in these cases is, not who is, but whether he, who 4 is, ought to be a citizen ; and there will still be a further 1276 a doubt, whether he who ought not to be a citizen is one in fact, for what ought not to be is what is false and is not. Now, there are some who hold office, and yet ought not to 5 hold office, whom we call rulers, although they rule unjustly. And the citizen was defined by the fact of his holding some kind of rule or office — he who holds a judicial or legislative! office fulfils our definition of a citizen. It is evident, there- fore, that the citizens about whom the doubt has arisen must * An untranslatable play upon the word Srjfii.ovp'/oi, which means either ' a magistrate ' or ' an artisan.' * Cp. c. I. § 12. ^ Inserting Kai before fUTo'iKovs with Bekker in his second edition. If Kai is omitted, as in all the MSS., we must translate — 'he enrolled in tribes many luetics, both strangers and slaves ' : or, ' he enrolled in tribes many strangers, and metics who had been slaves.* 104 When is a State the Samef III. 2 be called citizens ; whether they ought to be so or not is a question which is bound up with the previous enquiry ^. 3 A parallel question is raised respecting the state whether a certain act is or is not an act of the state ; for example, in the transition from an oligarchy or a tyranny to a democracy. 2 In such cases persons refuse to fulfil their contracts or any other obligations on the ground that the tyrant, and not the state, contracted them ; they argue that some constitutions are established by force, and not for the sake of the common good. But this would apply equally to democracies, for they too may be founded on violence, and then the acts of the democracy will be neither more nor less legitimate than those 3 of an oligarchy or of a tyranny. This question runs up into another — When shall we say that the state is the same, and when different ? It would be a very superficial view which considered only the place and the inhabitants ; for the soil and the population may be separated, and some of the inhabitants 4 may live in one place and some in another. This, however, is not a very serious difficulty ; we need only remark that the I word ' state ' is ambiguous, meaning both state and city. : )oM-*5u Wv-'I( ' It is further asked: When are men, living in the same h^ J"^' place, to be regarded as a single city — what is the limit ? 5 Certainly not the wall of the city, for you might surround all Peloponnesus v/ith a wall. But a city, having such vast circuit, would contain a nation rather than a state, like Baby- lon '^, which, as they say, had been taken for three days before { 6 some part of the inhabitants became aware of the fact. This difficulty may, however, with advantage be deferred' to . another occasion ; the statesman has to consider the size of 1 Cp. c. I. § I. 2 Cp. ii. 6. § 6. ^ Cp. vii. c. 4 and c. 5. when is a State the Samei lof A'^.^^^v, >_'^ the state, and whether it should consist of more than one III. 3 nation or not. Again, shall we say that while the race of inhabitants, as well as their place of abode, remain the same, the city is also the same, although the citizens are always dying and being born, as we call rivers and fountains the same, although the water is always flowing away and coming again ? Or shall we say that the generations of men, like the rivers, are the same, but that the state changes? For, since the state is 1276 b a community of citizens united by sharing in one form of f government, when the form of the government changes and | becomes different, then it may be supposed that the state is " no longer the same, just as a tragic differs from a comic chorus, although the members of both may be identical. And 8 in this manner we speak, of every union or composition of elements, when the form of their composition alters ; for example, harmony of the same sounds is said to be different, accordingly as the Dorian or the Phrygian mode is employed. And if this is true it is evident that the sameness of the state 9 consists chiefly in the sameness of the constitution, and may'^ be called or not called by the same name, whether the inhabi- tants are the same or entirely different. It is quite another question, whether a state ought or ought not to fulfil engage- ments when the form of government changes. There is a point nearly allied to the preceding : Whether 4 the virtue of a good man and a good cftizen is the same or not^. But, before entering on this discussion, we must first ' obtain some general notion of the virtue of the citizen. Like 3 the sailor, the citizen is a member of a community. Now, 2 sailors have different functions, for one of them is a rower, ' Cp. N. Eth. V. 2. § II. I 1 06 The Good JMari and III. 4 another a pilot, a third a look-out man, and a fourth is described by some similar term ; and while the precise definition of each individual's virtue applies exclusively to him, there is, at the same time, a common definition applicable to them all. For they have all of them a common object, which !is safety in navigation. Similarly, one citizen differs from another, but the sahation of the community is the common business of them all. This community is the state; the virtue of the citizen must therefore be relative to the constitution of which he is a member. If, then, there are many forms of government, it is evident that the virtue of the good citizen cannot be the one perfect virtue. But we say that the good 4 man is he who has perfect virtue. Hence it is evident that the good citizen need not of necessity possess the virtue which makes a good man. The same question may also be approached by another road, 5 from a consideration of the perfect state. If the state cannot be entirely composed of good men, and each citizen is expected to do his own business well, and must therefore have virtue, 1277 a inasmuch as all the citizens cannot be alike, the virtue of the citizen and of the good man cannot coincide. All must have the virtue of the good citizen — thus, and thus only, can the state be perfect ; but they will not have the virtue of a good I man, unless we assume that in the good state all the citizens must be good. 6 Again, the state may be compared to the living being : as the first elements into which the living being is resolved are soul and body, as the soul is made up of reason and appetite, the family of husband and wife, property of master and slave, so out of all these, as well as other dissimilar elements, the state is composed; and, therefore, the virtue of all the the Good Citi'^en 107 citizens cannot possibly be the same, any more than the III. 4 excellence of the leader of a chorus is the same as that of the performer who stands by his side. I have said enough to 7 show why the two kinds of virtue cannot be absolutely and ^^ always the same. But will there then be no case in which the virtue of the good citizen and the viitue of the goou man coincide ? To this we answer [not that the good citizen, but] that the good ruler is a good and wise man, and that he who would be a statesman must be a wise man. And some persons say that 8 even the education of the niler should be of a special kind ; v for are not the children of kings instructed in riding and military exercises ? As Euripides says : ' No subtle arts for me, but what the state requires '.' As though there were a special education needed by a ruler. If then the virtue of a good ruler is the same as that of a good 9 man, and we assume further that the subject is a citizen as well as the ruler, the virtue of the good citizen and the virtue of the good man cannot be always the same, although in some cases [i.e. in the perfect state] they may; for the virtue of a ruler differs from that of a citizen. It was the sense of this difference which made Jason say that ' he felt hungry when he was not a tyrant,' meaning that he could not endure to live in \ a private station. But, on the other hand, it may be argued 10 that men are praised for knowing both how to rule and how to obey, and he is said to be a citizen of approved virtue who ■ is able to do both. Now if we suppose the virtue of a good * man to be that which rules, and the virtue of the citizen to include ruling and obeying, it cannot be said that they are ' Fragment from the Aeolus, quoted in Stobaeus, 45. 13, ? io8 The Good Alan and III. 4 equally worthy of praise. Since, then, it is occasionally held " that the ruler and the ruled should learn different things and not the same things, and that the citizen must know and share .•H:iSi^ in both; the inference is obvious^J There is, indeed, the rule of a master which is concerned with menial office^ — the master need not know how to perform these, but may employ others in the execution of them : anything else would be 12 degrading; and by anything else I mean the menial duties which vary much in character and are executed by various classes of slaves, such, for example, as handicraftsmen, who, as their name signifies, live by the labour of their hands : — 1277 b under these the mechanic is included. Hence in ancient jtimes, and among some nations, the working classes had no ihare in the government — a privilege which they only acquired 13 under the extreme democracy. Certainly the good man and |tlie statesman and the good citizen ought not to learn the It • 9o'\ grafts of inferiors except for their own occasional use ' ; if 1^ they habitually practise them, there will cease to be a distinc- tion between master and slave. 14 This is not the rule of which we are speaking ; but there is a rule of another kind, which is exercised over freemen and equals by birth — a constitutional rule, which the ruler must learn by obeying, as he would learn the duties of a general of cavalry by being under the orders of a general of cavalry, or the duties of a general of infantry by being under the orders of a general of infantry, or by having had the command of a company or brigade. It has been well said that ' he who 15 has never learned to obey cannot be a good commander.' The * Viz. that some kind of previous subjection is an advantage to the ruler. Cp. infra, § 14. ' Cp. i, 7. §§ 2-5. * Cp. viii. 2. § 5. the Good Citizen 109 two are not the same, but the good citizen ought to be capable III. 4 of both ; he should know how to govern like a freeman, and; how to obey like a freeman — these are the virtues of a citizen. And, although the temperance and justice of a ruler are dis- i6 tinct fiom those of a subject, the virtue of a good man will include both ; for the good man, who is fiee and also a subject, will not have one virtue only, say justice, but he will have distinct kinds of virtue, the one qualifying him to rule, the other to obey, and differing as the temperance and courage of men and women differ^. For a man would be thought a i? N* 5"! coward if he had no more courage than a courageous woman, and a woman would be thought loquacious if she imposed no more restraint on her conversation than the good man ; and indeed their part in the management of the household is different, for the duty of the one is to acquire, and of the other to preserve. Practical wisdom only is characteristic of the ruler '^ : it would seem that all other virtues must equally ^' belong to ruler and subject. The virtue of the subject is 18 certainly not wisdom, but only true opinion ; he may be com- "^ 1^ pared to the maker of the flute, while his master is like the flute-player or user of the flute '. From these considerations may be gathered the answer to the question, whether the virtue of the good man is the same as that of the good citizen, or different, and how far the same, and how far different *. <^' ^* '^'' '^'' ^7 There still remains one more question about the citizen : 5 Is he only a true citizen who has a share of office, or is the mechanic to be included ? If they who hold no office are to be deemed citizens, not every citizen can have this virtue of 1 Cp. i. 13. § 9. * Cp. Rep. iv. 428. '■' Cp. Rep. x. 601 d, e. ♦ Cp. c. 5. § 10; c. 18. § I ; iv. 7. § 2 ; vii. 14. § 8. 1 1 o Are Mechanics Citi'X^ens f* III. 5 ruling and obeying ^ which makes a citizen ^ And if none of the lower class are citizens, in which part of the state are they to be placed ? For they are not resident aliens, and they 1278 a are not foreigners. To this objection may we not reply, that there is no more absurdity in excluding them than in excluding slaves and freedmen from any of the above-mentioned classes ? It must be admitted that we cannot consider all those to be y citizens who are necessary to the existence of the state; for example, children are not citizens equally with grown up men, who are citizens absolutely, but children, not being grown up, 3 are only citizens in a qualified sense. Doubtless in ancient times, and among some nations, the artisan class were slaves or foreigners, and therefore the majority of them are so now. The best form of state will not admit them to citizenship ; but if they are admitted, then our definition of the virtue of a citizen will apply to some citizens and freemen only, and 4 not to those who work for their living. The latter class, to whom toil is a necessity, are either slaves who minister to the wants of individuals, or mechanics and labourers who are the servants of the community. These reflections carried a little further will explain their position ; and indeed what has been said already is of itself explanation enough. & Since there are many forms of government there must be |many varieties of citizens, and especially of citizens who are Ba4»2tr rft V KV . subjects ; so that under some governments the mechanic and W. >7 6 ^'^^ labourer will be citizens, but not in others, as, for example, * Or, ' for this man (i.e. the meaner sort of man) is a citizen and does not exercise rule ' (see below, § 3, d Z\ koX ovtos TroXhrjs). According to the way of taking the passage which is followed in the text, ovtos = 6 (xojv rfjv ToiavTr]v dperT/y : according to the second way, it refers to ^dvavffos. Different Kjnds of Citi^fis III in aristocracy or the so-called government of the best (if there III. * be such an one), in which honours are given according to virtue and merit ; for no man can practise virtue who is living j the life of a mechanic or labourer. In oligarchies the qualifi- 6 cation for office is high, and therefore no labourer can ever be a citizen ; but a mechanic may, for many of them are rich. . . At Thebes ^ there was a law that no man could hold office 7 who had not retired from business for ten years. In many states the law goes to the length of admitting aliens ; for in some democracies a man is a citizen though his mother only be a citizen [and his father an alien] ; and a similar principle is applied to illegitimate children ; the law is relaxed when 8 there is a dearth of population. But when the number of citizens increases, first the children of a male or a female slave ' are excluded ; then those whose mothers only are citizens ; and at last the right of citizenship is confined to those whose fathers and mothers are both citizens. Hence, as is evident, there are different kinds of citizens ; 9 and he is a citizen in the highest sense who shares in the honours of the state. In the poems of Homer [Achilles complains of Agamemnon treating him] ' like some dishonoured stranger ^ ; ' for he who is excluded from the honours of the state is no better than an alien. But when this exclusion is concealed, then the object is to deceive one's fellow-country- men. As to the question whether the virtue of the good man is the 1-27S b same as that of the good citizen, the considerations already '° |f *^9 adduced prove that in some states the two are the same, and • ^^VOs^ W in others different. When they are the same it is not the virtue of every citizen which is the same as that of the good ' Cp. vi. 7. § 4. a II. ix. 648. fft ^••f/' u$ 112 Government True and 'Perverted III. 5 man, but only the virtue of the statesman and of those who have or may have, alone or in conjunction with others, the conduct of public affairs. 6 Having determined these questions, we have next to con- sider whether there is only one form of government or many, and if many, what they are, and how many, and what are the differences between them. i-Q A constitution is the ariangement of magistracies in a state^, especially of the highest of all. The government is every- where sovereign in the state, and the constitution is in fact the 2 government. For example, in democracies the people are supreme, but in oligarchies, the few; and, therefore, we say that these two forms of government are different : and so in other cases. First, let us consider what is the pui-pose of a state, and how many forms of government there are by which human 3 society is regulated. We have already said, in the former part of this treatise^, when drawing a distinction between household-management and the rule of a master, that man is _byjiature a political animal. And therefore, men, even when they do not require one another's help, desire to live together all the same, and are in fact brought together by their common interests in proportion as they severally attain to any measure 4 of well-being. This is certainly the chief end, both of indi- viduals and of states. And also for the sake of mere life (in which there is possibly some noble element) mankind meet together and maintain the political community, so long as the 5 evils of existence do not greatly overbalance the good ^ And we all see that men cling to life even in the midst of » Cp. c. 1. § I ; iv. I. § lo. 2 cp. i. 2. §§ 9, lo. ' Cp. Plato, Polit. 302 A. Government True and Perverted 113 misfortune, seeming to find in it a natural sweetness and III. 6 happiness. There is no difficulty in distinguishing the various kinds of authority; they have been often defined already in popular works ^ The rule of a master, although the slave by nature 6 and the master by nature have in reality the same interests, is nevertheless exercised primarily with a view to the interest of the master, but accidentally considers the slave, since, if the ^, slave perish, the rule of the master perishes with him. On 7 the other hand, the government of a wife and children and of a household, which we have called household-management, is exercised in the first instance for the good of the governed or for the common good of both parties, but essentially for the good of the governed, as we see to be the case in medicine, 1279 a gymnastics, and the arts in general, which are only accidentally concerned with the good of the artists themselves^. (For there is no reason why tlie trainer may not sometimes practise gymnastics, and the pilot is always one of the crew.) The 8 trainer or the pilot considers the good of those committed to his care. But, when he is one of the persons taken care of, he accidentally participates in the advantage, for the pilot is also a sailor, and the trainer becomes one of those in training. And so in politics : when the state is framed upon the prin- 9 ciple of equality and likeness, the citizens think that they ought to hold office by turns. In the order of nature every one would take his turn of service ; and then again, somebody else would look after his interest, just as he, while in office, had looked after theirs^. [That was originally the way.] But nowadays, for the sake of the advantage which is to be '© * Or, 'in our popular works.' ^ Cp. Plato, Rep. i. 341 d. ' Cp. ii. 2. §§ 6, 7. 114 Classification of Governments III. 6 gained from the public revenues and from office, men want to be always in office. One might imagine that the rulers, being sickly, were only kept in health while they continued in office; in that case we may be sure that they would be hunting II after places. The conclusion is evident: that governments, 'which have a regard to the common interest, are constituted in accordance with strict principles of justice, and are there- fore true forms ; but those which regard only the interest of the mlers are all defective and perverted forms, for they arc despotic, whereas a state is a community of freemen, 7 Having determined these points, we have next to consider how many forms of government there are, and what they are ; and in the first place what are the true forms, for when they are determined the perversions of them will at once be 2 apparent. The words constitution and government have the -^same meaning, and the government, which is the supreme authority in states, must be in the hands of one, or of a few, "- or of many. The true forms of government, therefore, are those in which the one, or the few, or the many, govern with a view to the common interest; but governments which rule with a view to the private interest, whether of the one, or of the few, or of the many, are perversions ^. For citizens, if they are truly citizens, ought to participate in the advantages I, of a state. Of forms of government in which one rules, we 3 call that which regards the common interests, kingship or royalty ; that in which more than one, but not many, rule, aristocracy [the rule of the best] ; and it is so called, either because the rulers are the best men, or because they have at heart the best interests of the state and of the citizens. But ||: when the citizens at large administer the state for the common 1 Cp. Eth. viii. lo (I. Classification of Governments 1 1 y interest, the government is called by the generic name — a III. 7 constitution [TroXirfia], And there is a reason for this use of language. One man or a few may excel in virtue ; but of 4 virtue there are many kinds : and as the number increases it becomes more difficult for them to attain perfection in every 1279 b kind, though they may in military virtue, for this is found in the masses. Hence, in a constitutional government the \ fighting- men have the supreme power, and those who possess arms are the citizens. Of the above-mentioned forms, the perversions are as 5 follows : — of royalty, tyranny ; of aristocracy, oligarchy ; of constitutional government, democracy. For tyranny is a kind of monarchy which has in view the interest of the monarch only ; oligarchy has in view the interest of the wealthy ; democracy, of the needy : none of them the common good of all. But there are difficulties about these forms of government, 8 and it will therefore be necessary to state a little more at length the nature of each of them. For he who would make a philosophical study of the various sciences, and does not regard practice only, ought not to overlook or omit anything, but to set forth the truth in every particular. Tyranny, as 2 I was saying, is monarchy exercising the rule of a master over political society ; oligarchy is when men of property have the government in their hands ; democracy, the opposite, when the indigent, and not the men of property, are the rulers. And here arises the first of our difficulties, and it 3 relates to the definition just given. For democracy is said to be the government of the many. But what if the many are men of property and have the power in their liands I In like manner oligarchy is said to be the government of the few; but I 2 I I 6 Oligarchy and Democracy Defined III. 8 what if the poor are fewer than the rich, and have the power in their hands because they are stronger ? In these cases the distinction which we have drawn between these different forms of government would no longer hold good. 4 Suppose, once more, that we add wealth to the few and poverty to the many, and name the governments accordingly — an oligarchy is said to be that in which the few and the wealthy, and a democracy that in which the many and the 5 poor are the rulers — there will still be a difficulty. For, if the only forms of government are the ones already mentioned, how shall we describe those other governments also just mentioned by us, in which the rich are the more numerous and the poor are the fewer, and both govern in their re- spective states ? 6 The argument seems to show that, whether in oligarchies or in democracies, the number of the governing body, whether the greater number, as in a democracy, or the smaller number, as in an oligarchy, is an accident due to the fact that the rich everywhere are few, and the poor numerous. But if so, there is a misapprehension of the causes of the difference 7 between them. For the real difference between democracy 1280 a| and oligarchy is poverty and wealth. Wherever men rule ' by reason of their wealth, whether they be few or many, that is an oligarchy, and where the poor rule, that is a demo- cracy. But as a fact the rich are few and the poor many : for few are well-to-do, whereas freedom is enjoyed by all, 1 and wealth and freedom are the grounds on which the I oligarchical and democratical parties respectively claim power ' in the state. ■jS ^Tl/Q Let us begin by considering the common definitions of . 0 oligarchy and democracy, and what is justice oligarchical and Political Justice 117 democratical. For all men cling to justice of some kind, but III. 9 their conceptions are imperfect and they do not express the whole idea. For example, justice is thought by them to be, and is, eguality, not, however, for all, but only for ec^uals. And ineq^uality is thought to be, and is, justice ; neither is 2 this for all, but only for unequals. When the persons are omitted, then men judge erroneously. The reason is that they are passing judgment on themselves, and most people are bad judges in their own case. And whereas justice 3 implies a relation to persons as well as to things, and a just distribution, as I have already said in the Ethics ', embraces alike persons and things, they acknowledge the equality of the things, but dispute about the merit of the persons, chiefly for the reason which I have just given — because they are bad judges in their own affairs ; and secondly, because both the parties to the argument are speaking of a limited and partial -y justice, but imagine themselves to be speaking of absolute justice. For those who are unequal in one respect, for 4 example wealth, consider themselves to be unequal in all ; and any who are equal in one respect, for example freedom, . consider themselves to be equal in all. But they leave out the capital point. For if men met and associated out of 5 regard to wealth only, their share in the state would be proportioned to their property, and the oligarchical doctrine would then seem to carry the day. It would not be just that he who paid one mina sliould have the same share of a hundred minae, '^ whether of the principal or of the profits -, as he who paid the remaining ninety-nine. But a state 6 1 N. Eth. V. 3. § 4. ^ Or, with Bernays, ' either ia the case of the original contributors or their suCLesso;s.' 1 1 8 The End of the State III. 9 exists for the sake of a good life, and not for the sake of life •" only : if life only were the object, slaves and brute animals I might form a state, but they cannot, for they have no share in happiness or in a life of free choice. Nor does a state exist for the sake of alliance and security from injustice ^, nor yet for the sake of exchange and mutual intercourse; for then the Tyrrhenians and the Carthaginians, and all who have commercial treaties with one another, would be the citizens of 7 one state. True, they have agreements about imports, and en- gagements that they will do no wrong to one another, and 1280 b written articles of alliance. But there are no magistracies common to the contracting parties who will enforce their engagements ; different states have each their own magistracies. Nor does one state take care that the citizens of the other are such as they ought to be, nor see that those who come under the terms of the treaty do no wrong or wickedness at . all, but only that tliey do no injustice to one another. 8 Whereas, those who care for good government take into consideration [the larger question of] virtue and vice in states. Whence it may be further inferred that '^virtue must be the serious care of a state which truly deserves the name'^: for [without this ethical end] the community becomes a mere alliance which differs only in place from alliances of which the members live apart; and law is only a convention, 'a surety to one another of justice,' as the sophist Lycophron says, and has no real power to make the citizens good and just. 9 This is obvious ; for suppose distinct places, such as 1 Cp. c. I. §4. ^ Or, ' virtue must be the care of a state which is truly so called, and not nietely in name.' T-he End of the State 119 Corinth and Megara, to be united by a wall, still they would m. 9 not be one city, not even if the citizens had the right to lo intermany, which is one of the rights peculiarly characteristic of states. Again, if men dwelt at a distance from one another, but not so far off as to have no intercourse, and there were laws among them that they should not wrong each other in their exchanges, neither would this be a state. Let us suppose that one man is a carpenter, another a husbandman, another a shoemaker, and so on, and that their number is ten thousand : nevertheless, if they have nothing in \ common but exchange, alliance, and the like, that would not ! constitute a state. Why is this ? Surely not because they 1 1 are at a distance from one another : for even supposing that such a community were to meet in one place, and that each man had a house of his own, which was in a manner his state, and that they made alliance with one another, but only against evil-doers ; still an accurate thinker would not deem this to be a state, if their intercourse with one another was of the same character after as before their union. It is clear 12 then that a state is not a mere society, having a common place, established for the prevention of crime and for the sake of exchange. These are conditions without which a state cannot exist ; but all of them together do not constitute a state, _which is a community of well-being in famihes and, aggregations of families, for the sake of a perfect and self-^ sufficing life. Such a community can only be established 13' among those who live in the same place and intermarry. Hence arise in cities family connexions, brotherhoods, common sacrifices, amusements which draw men together. They are created by friendship, for friendship is the motive of society. The end is the good life, and these are the :-f I 20 Sovereignty III. 9 means towards it. And the state is the union of families and 14 villages having for an end a perfect and self-sufficing life, by which we mean a happy and honourable life ^. Our conclusion, then, is that political society exists for tlie 15 sake of noble actions, and not of mere companionship. And they who contribute most to such a society have a greater 1 share in it than those who have the same or a greater freedom \ or nobility of birth but are inferior to them in political virtue ; i or than those who exceed them in wealth but are surpassed ':^ by them in virtue. From what has been said it will be clearly seen that all the partisans of different forms of government speak of a part of justice only. 10 There is also a doubt as to what is to be the supreme power in the state : — Is it the multitude ? Or the wealthy ? Or the good ? Or the one best man ? Or a tyrant ? Any of these alternatives seems to involve disagreeable conse- quences. If the poor, for example, because they are more in number, divide among themselves the property of the rich, is not this unjust ? No, by heaven (will be the reply), for 2 the lawful authority [i. e. the people] willed it. But if this is not injustice, pray what is ? Again, when [in the first division] all has been taken, and the majority divide anew the property of the minority, is it not evident, if this goes on, that they will ruin the state ? Yet surely, virtue is not the ruin of those who possess her, nor is justice destructive of \, a state '^; and therefore this law of confiscation clearly cannot 3 be just. If it were, all the acts of a tyrant must of necessity oe just ; for he only coerces other men by superior power, !just as the multitude coerce the rich. But is it just, then, 1 Co. i. 2. § 8; N. Eth, i. 7. § 6. * Cp. Plato, Rep. i. 351, 352. Sovereimty of the People 121 that the few and the wealthy should be the rulers ? And III. 10 what if they, in like manner, rob and plunder the people — is this just ? If so, the other case [i. e. the case of the majority plundering the minority] will likewise be just. But 4 there can be no doubt that all these things are wrong and unjust. Then ought the good to rule and have supreme power ? But in that case everybody else, being excluded from power, will be dislionoured. For the offices of a state are posts of honour; and if one set of men always hold them, the rest*^ must be deprived of them. Then will it be well that the one ^5 best man should rule ? Nay, that is still more oligarchical, for the number of those who are dishonoured is thereby increased. Some one may say that it is bad for a man, subject as he is to all the accidents of human passion, to have the supreme power, rather than the law. But what if the law itself be democratical or oligarchical, how will that help us out of our difficulties ^ ? Not at all ; the same conse- quences will follow. Most of these questions may be reserved for another U occasion. The principle that the multitude ought to be supreme rather than the few best is capable of a satisfactory explanation, and, though not free from difficulty, yet seems to contain an element of truth. For the many, of whom each 2 individual is but an ordinary person, when they meet together 1281 b may very likely be better than the few good, if regarded not individually but collectively, just as a feast to which many contribute is better than a dinner provided out of a single ' purse. For each individual among the many has a share of virtue and prudence, and when they meet together they * Cp. c. II. § 20. 122 Treasons for and against III. 11 become in a manner one man, who has many feet, and hands, '^- and senses ; that is a figure of their mind and disposition. 3 iHence the many are better judges than a single man of music 4nd poetry ; for some understand one part, and some another, 4 land among them, they understand the whole. There is a similar combination of qualities in good men, who differ from any individual of the many, as the beautiful are said to differ from those v/ho are not beautiful, and works of art from realities, because in them the scattered elements are combined, although, if taken separately, the eye of one person or some other feature in another person would be fairer than 5 in the picture. Whether this principle can apply to every democracy, and to all bodies of men, is not clear. Or rather, by heaven, in some cases it is impossible of application ; for the argument would equally hold about brutes ; and wherein, it will be asked, do some men differ from brutes ? But there may be bodies of men about whom our statement is neverthe- 6 less true. And if so, the difficulty which has been already raised, and also another which is akin to it — viz. what power should be assigned to the mass of freemen and citizens, who are not rich and have no personal merit — are both solved. 7 Tliere is still a danger in allowing them to share the great offices of state, for their folly will lead them into error, and their dishonesty into crime. But there is a danger also in not letting them share, for a state in which many poor men are 8 excluded from office will necessarily be full of enemies. The only way of escape is to assign to them some deliberative and judicial functions. For this reason Solon ^ and certain other .legislators give them the power of electing to offices, and of calling the magistrates to account, but they do not allow 1 Cp, ii. 12. § 5. Sovereigfity of the People 123 them to liold oiBce singly. When they meet together their III. 11 perceptions are quite good enough, and combined with the 9 better class they are useful to the state (just as impure . food when mixed with what is pure sometimes makes the entire mass more wholesome than a small quantity of the pure would be), but each individual, left to himself, forms an imperfect judgment. On the other hand, the popular lo fonnjpf^government involves certain difficulties. In the first place, it might be objected that he who can judge of the healing of a sick man would be one who could himself heal his disease, and make him whole — that is, in other words, the physician ; and so in all professions and arts. 1282 a. As, then, the physician ought to be called to account by physicians, so ought men in general to be called to account by their peers. But physicians are of three kinds: — there 11 is the apothecary, and there is the physician of the higher class, and thirdly the intelligent man who has studied the art : in all arts there is such a class ; and we attribute the power of judging to them quite as much as to professors of the art. Now, does not the same principle apply to 12 elections ? For a right election can only be made by those who have knowledge; a geometrician, for example, will choose rightly in matters of geometry, or a pilot in matters of steering ; and, even if there be some occupations and arts with which private persons are familia;-, they certainly cannot judge better than those who know. So that, according 13 to this argument, neither the election of magistrates, nor the calling of them to account, should be entrusted to the many, i^ Yet possibly these objections are to a great extent met by our old answer, that if the people are not utterly degraded, although individually they may be worse judges than those 124 J^aso?2s for and against III. 11 who have special knowledge — as a body they are as good or better. Moreover, there are some artists whose works are judged of solely, or in the best manner, not by them- selves, but by those who do not possess the art ; for example, the knowledge of the house is not limited to the builder only; the user, or, in other words, the master, of the .^ house will even be a better judge than the builder, just as the pilot will judge better of a rudder than the carpenter, and the guest will judge better of a feast than the cook. 15 This difficulty seems now to be sufficiently answered, but there is another akin to it. That inferior persons should have authority in greater matters than the good would appear to be a strange thing, yet the election and calling to account of the magistrates is the greatest of all. And these, as I was saying, are functions which in some states are assigned to the people, for the assembly is supreme in all such matters. 16 Yet persons of any age, and having but a sniall property qualification, sit in the assembly and delibeiate and judge, although for the great officers of state, such as controllers and generals, a high qualification is required. This difficulty may be solved in the same manner as the preceding, and the present practice of democracies may be really defensible. 17 For the power does not reside in the dicast, or senator, or ecclesiast, but in the court and the senate, and the assembly, of which individual senators, or ecclesiasts, or 18 dicasts, are only parts or members. And for this reason the many may claim to have a higher authority than the few ; for the people, and the senate, and the courts consist of many persons, and their property collectively is greater than the property of one or of a few individuals holding great offices. But enoush of this. Equality and Inequality 125- The discussion of the first question ^ shows nothing so HI. 11 clearly as that laws, when good, should be supreme; and '9 that the magistrate or magistrates should regulate those , matters only on which the laws are unable to speak with ■ precision owing to the difficulty of any general principle embracing all particulars ". But what are good laws has 20 not yet been clearly explained; the old difficulty remains •''. The goodness or badness, justice or injustice, of laws is of necessity relative to the constitutions of states. But if 21 so, true forms of government will of necessity have just laws,>. and perverted forms of government will have unjust laws. In all sciences and arts the end is a good, and especially and 12 above all in the highest of all * — this is the political science of which the good is justice, in other words, the common 1 interest. All men think justice to be a sort of equality ; and to a certain extent ^ they agree in the philosophical distinctions which have been laid down by us about Ethics*. For they admit that justice is a thing having relation to persons, and that equals ought to have equality. But there still re- 2 mains a question — equality or inequality of what? Here is a difficulty which the political philosopher has to resolve. For very likely some persons will say that offices of state ought to be unequally distributed according to superior excellence, in whatever respect, of the citizen, although there is no other difference between him and the rest of the community ; for that those who differ in any one respect have different rights and claims. But, surely, if this is true, the complexion or 3 height of a man, or any other advantage, will be a reason 1 Cp. c. 10. § I. * Cp. N. Eth. V. 10. § 4. s__Cp^c. 10. § 5. ■* Cp. i. I. § I ; N. Eth. i. i. § I. * Cp7c79. § I. « Cp. N. Eth. V. 3. 1 2d Covfiicting Claims III. 12 for his obtaining a greater share of political rights. The 4 error here lies upon the surface, and may be illustrated from tthe other arts and sciences. When a number of flute-players are equal in their art, there is no reason why those of them who are better born should have better flutes given to them ; for they will not play any better on the flute, and the superior instrument should be reserved for him who is the superior artist. If what I am saying is still obscure, it will be made 5 clearer as we proceed. For if there were a superior flute- player who was far inferior in birth and beauty, although either of these may be a greater good than the art of flute- playing, and persons gifted with these qualities may excel the flute-player in a greater ratio than he excels them in his art, 1283 a still he ought to have the best flutes given to him, unless the advantages of wealth and birth contribute to excellence 6 in flute-playing, which they do not. Moreover upon this principle any good may be compared with any other. For if a given height, then height in general may be measured either against height or against freedom. Thus if A excels in height more than B in virtue, and height in general is more excellent than virtue, all things will be commensurable [which is absurd] ; for if a ceitain magnitude is greater than some otlier, it Is clear that some other will be equal. 7 But since no such comparison can be made, it is evident that there is good reason why in politics men do not ground their claim to oflice on every sort of inequality any more than in the arts. For if some be slow, and others swift, that is no reason why the one should have little and the others much; it is in gymnastic contests that such excellence is 8 rewarded. Whereas the rival claims of candidates for office can only be based on the possession of elements which enter to Sovereign Power 127 o into the composition of a state, [such as wealth, virtue, etc.]. III. 12 And therefore the noble, or freeborn, or rich, may with good reason claim office ; for holders of offices must be freemen and tax-payers : a state can be no more composed entirely of poor men th^ln entirely of slaves. But if wealth 9 and freedom are necessary elements, justice and valour are equally so ^ ; for without the former a state cannot exist at all, without the latter not well. If the existence of the state is alone to be considered, then 13 it would seem that all, or some at least, of these claims are just ; but, if we take into account a good life, as I have already said-, education and virtue have superior claims.N As, however, those who are equal in one thing ought not to | be equal in all, nor those who are unequal in one thing to j be unequal in all, it is certain that all forms of govern- ment which rest on either of these principles are perversions. ^ All men have a claim in a certain sense, as 1 have already a admitted, but they have not an absolute claim. The rich claim because they have a greater share in the land, and land is the common element of the state ; also they are generally more trustworthy in contracts. The free claim under the same title as the noble ; for they are nearly akin. And the noble are citizens in a truer sense than the ignoble, since good birth is always valued in a man's own home and country'. Another reason is, that those who are sprung from better 13 ancestors are likely to be better men, for nobility is excellence j of race. Virtue, too, may be truly said to have a claim, for '' justice has been acknowledged by us to be a social * virtue, and it implies all others ^ Again, the many may urge their 4 1 Cp. iv. 4. §§ 12-16. 2 cp. c. 9. §§ 14, 15. 2 Cp. i. 6. § 7. ■* Cp. i. i. § 16. ' Cp. N. Eth. v. i. § 15. 128 Co7iflicting claims to Power III. 13 claim against the few ; for, when taken collectively, and compared with the few, they are stronger and richer and 1283 b better. But, what if the good, the rich, the noble, and the other classes who make up a state, are all living together in the same city; will there, or will there not, be any doubt 5 who shall rule ? — No doubt at all in determining who ought to rule in each of the above-mentioned forms of government. For states are characterized by diflerences in their governing bodies — one of them has a government of the rich, another of the virtuous, and so on. But a difficulty arises when all 6 these elements coexist. How are we to decide ? Suppose the virtuous to be very few in number : may we consider their numbers in relation to their duties, and ask whether they are enough to administer the state, or must they be so many as will make up a state ? Objections may be urged against all 7 the aspirants to political power. For those who found their ^claims on wealth or family have no basis of justice; on this principle, if any one person were richer than all the rest, it is clear that he ought to be the ruler of them. In like manner he who is very distinguished by his birth ought to have the superiority over all those who claim on the ground that they are 8 freeborn. In an aristocracy, or government of the best, a like difficulty occurs about virtue ; for if one citizen be better than the other members of the government, however good they may be, he too, upon the same principle of justice, should rule over them. And if the people are to be supreme because they are stronger than the few, then if one man, or more than one, but not a majority, is stronger than the many, they ought to rule, and not the many. 9 All these considerations appear to show that none of the principles on wliich men claim to rule, and hold all Conjiicting Claims to Power 129 other men in subjection to them, are strictly right. To III. 13 those who claim to be the masters of state on the ground ^o of their virtue or their wealth, the many might fairly answer that they themselves are often better and richer than the few — I do not say individually, but collectively. And ir another ingenious objection which is sometimes put forward may be met in a similar manner. Some persons doubt whether the legislator who desires to make the justest laws ought to legislate with a view to the good of the higher classes or of the many, when the case which we have mentioned occurs [i. e. when all the elements coexist ^]. Now what is just or right is to be interpreted in the sense la of ' what is equal ' ; and that which is right in the sense of being equal is to be considered with reference to the advantage of the state, and the common good of the citizens. And a citizen is one who shares in governing and being governed. He differs under different forms of government, 1284 a but in the best state he is one who is able and willing to be governed and to govern with a view to the life of virtue. If, however, there be some one person, or more than one, 13 although not enough to make up the full complement of a state, whose virtue is so pre-eminent that the virtues or the political capacity of all the rest admit of no comparison with his or theirs, he or they can be no longer regarded as part of a state ; for justice will not be done to the superior, if he is reckoned only as the equal of those who are so far inferior to him in virtue and in political capacity. Such an one may truly be deemed a God among men. Hence we see that 14 legislation is necessarily concerned only with those who are equal in birth and in powei- ; and that for men of pre-eminent * Cp. § 4. I30 The One Best Man i7q III. 13 virtue there is no law — they are themselves a law. Any one would be ridiculous who attempted to make laws for them : they would probably retort what, in the fable of Antisthenes, the lions said to the hares [' where are your claws ? '], when in the council of the beasts the latter began haranguing 15 and claiming equality for all. And for this reason democratic states have instituted ostracism ; equality is above all things their aim, and therefore they ostracise and banish from Uhe city for a time those who seem to predominate too much through their wealth, or the number of their friends, or 16 through any other political influence. Mythology tells us that the Argonauts left Heracles behind for a similar reason ; the ship Argo would not take him because she feared that he would have been too much for the rest of the crew. Wherefore those who denounce tyranny and blame the counsel which Periander gave to Thrasybulus cannot be held altogether just in ly their censure. The story is that Periander, when the herald was sent to ask counsel of him, said nothing, but only cut off the tallest ears of corn till he had brought the field to a level. The herald did not know the meaning of the action, but came and reported what he had seen to Thrasybulus, who understood that he was to cut off the principal men in the 18 state*; and this is a policy not only expedient for tyrants or in practice confined to them, but equally necessary in ^oligarchies and democracies. Ostracism '^ is a measure of the I same kind, which acts by disabling and banishing the most 1 9' prominent citizens. Great powers do the same to whole cities and nations, as the Athenians did to the Samians, Chians, and Lesbians ; no sooner had they obtained a firm grasp of the empire, than they humbled their allies contrary » Cp. V. 10. § 13. " Cp. V. 3. § 3. Ostracism 131 to treaty ; and the Persian king has repeatedly crushed the m. 13 Medes, Babylonians, and other nations, when their spirit has 1284 b been stirred by the recollection of their former greatness. The problem is a universal one, and equally concerns all 20 forms of government, true as well as false; for, although perverted forms with a view to their own interests may adopt this policy, those which seek the common interest do so likewise. The same thing may be observed in the arts 21 and sciences ^ ; for the painter will not allow the figure to have a foot which, however beautiful, is not in proportion, nor will the ship-builder allow the stern or any other part of the vessel to be unduly large, any more than the chorus- master will allow any one who sings louder or better than all the rest to sing in the choir. ^ Monarchs, too, may practise 22 compulsion and still live in harmony with their cities, if their government is for the interest of the state '^. Hence where there is an acknowledged superiority the argument in| favour of ostracism is based upon a kind of political justice.) It would certainly be better that the legislator should from the 33 first so order his state as to have no need of such a remedy. But if the need arises, the next best thing is that he should endeavour to correct the evil by this or some similar measure. The principle, however, has not been fairly applied in states ; for, instead of looking to the public good, they have used ostracism for factious purposes. It is true that under perverted 24 forms of government, and from their special point of view, such a measure is just and expedient, but it is also clear that ^ it is not absolutely just. In the perfect state there would be * Cp. V. 3. § 6 ; 9. § 7 ; vii. 4. § 10 ; Rep. iv, 420. * Or, ' Monarchies do not differ in this respect (i. e. the employment of compulsion) from free states, but their government must be,' etc. K 2 132 Kjn^y T^l^ III. 13 great doubts about the use of it, not when appHed to excess in strength, wealth, popularity, or the like, but when used against some one who is pre-eminent in virtue, — what is to 25 be done with him ? Mankind will not say that such an one is to be expelled and exiled ; on the other hand, he ought not to be a subject — that would be as if men should claim to rule over Zeus on the principle of rotation of office. The only alternative is that all should joyfully obey such a ruler, according to what seems to be the order of nature, and that men like him should be kings in their state for life. ?• /■/»• /C>^> 14 The preceding discussion, by a natural transition, leads to the consideration of royalty, which we admit to be one of the true forms of government ^. Let us see whether in order to be well governed a state or country should be under the rule of a king or under some other form of government ; and whether monarchy, although good for some, may not be 2 bad for others. But first we must determine whether there is 1285 a one species of royalty or many. It is not easy to see that there are many, and that the manner of government is not the same in all of them. 13 (i) Of royalties according to law, the Lacedaemonian is ' . ^ thought to answer best to the true pattern ; but there the royal /^cio, 0) ►W/VoT^ ■ power is not absolute, except when the kings go on an O^i^ 'expedition, and then they take the command. Matters of ' 4 religion are likewise committed to them. The kingly office is \ in truth a kind of generalship, irresponsible and perpetual. ^ The king has not the power of life and death, except ^ * ii. 9. § 29. ^ Omitting tV rivi BaaiKda, which is bracketed by Bekker in his 2nd edit. Varieties of Kjngly T{ule 133 when upon a campaign and in the field ; after the manner of III. 14 the ancients which is described in Homer. For Agamemnon is patient when he is attacked in the assembly, but when the army goes out to battle he has the power even of life and death. Does he not say ? — 5 ' When I find a man skulking apart from the battle, nothing shall save him from the dogs and vultures, for in my hands is death ^' This, then, is one form of royalty — a generalship for life : and of such royalties some are hereditary and others elective. US There is another sort of monarchy not uncommon 6. ■" ' among the barbarians, which nearly resembles tyranny. But /W-eSMfr^^ are, and whence they arise, I will now proceed to consider, starting from the principle already admitted \ which is that 8 every state consists, not of one, but of many parts. If we were going to speak of the different species of animals, we should first of all determine the organs which are indispens- able to every animal, as for example some organs of sense and instruments of receiving and digesting food, such as the mouth and the stomach, besides organs of locomotion. As- suming now that there are only so many kinds of organs, but that there may be differences in them — I mean different kinds of mouths, and stomachs, and perceptive and locomotive organs — the possible combinations of these differences will necessarily furnish many varieties of animals. (For animals ' Cp. c. 3. § I. Essential Elements of the State 15-3 cannot be the same which have different kinds of mouths or IV. 4 of ears.) And when all the combinations are exhausted, there will be as many sorts of animals as there are combina- tions of the necessary oigans. In like manner the forms of 9 government which have been described, as I have repeatedly said, are composed, not of one, but of many elements. C[^ne , .u^., ...i-^t «tAt element_is the food-producing class, who are called husband- «, men; a second, a class of mechanics, who practise the arts r291a without which a city cannot exist ; — of these arts some are absolutely necessary, otliers contribute to luxury or to the ^ U . grace of life. The third class is that of traders, and by traders i^ ' I mean those who are engaged in buying and selling, whether in commerce or in retail trade. _A fourth class is that of the serfs or labourers. The warriors make up the fifth class, and they are as necessary as any of the others, if the country is not to be the slave of every invader. For how can a state which n has any title to the name be of a slavish nature ? The state is independent and self-sufficing, but a slave is the reverse of inde- pendent. Hence we see that this subject, though ingeniously, has not been satisfactorily treated in the Republic ^. Socrates 12 says that a state is made up of four sorts of people who are absolutely necessary; these are a weaver, a husbandman, a shoemaker, and a builder ; afterwards, finding that they are not enough, he adds a smith, and again a herdsman, to look after the necessary animals ; then a merchant, and then a retaiHrader. All these together form the complement of the ' 3 firsf state, as if a state were established merely to supply the necessaries of life, rather than for the sake of the good, or stood equally in need of shoemakers and of husbandmen. But he does not admit into the state a military class until the * Rep. ii. 369. 15-4 Essential Elements of the State IV. 4 country has increased in size, and is beginning to encroach on its neighbour's land, whereupon they go to war. Yet even amongst his four original citizens, or whatever be the number of those whom he associates in the state, there must be some vone who will dispense justice and determine what is just. 14 And as the soul may be said to be more truly part of an animal than the body, so the higher parts of states, that is to say, the warrior class, the class engaged in the administration of justice, and in deliberation, which is the special business of political common sense, — these are more essential to the state than the parts which minister to the necessaries of life. 15 Whether their several functions are the functions of different citizens, or of the same — for it may often happen that the same persons are both warriors and husbandmen — is imma- terial to the argument. The higher as well as the lower elements are to be equally considered parts of the state, and if so, the military element must be included. There are also \the wealthy who minister to the state with their property; leVhese form the seventh class. The eighth class is that of magistrates and of officers ; for the state cannot exist without rulers. And therefore some must be able to take office and to 17 serve the state, either always or in turn. There only remains the class of those who deliberate and who judge between dis- putants ; we were just now distinguishing them. If the fair and equitable organization of all these elements is necessary to 1291 b states, then there must also be persons who have the ability of 18 statesmen. ' Many are of opinion that different functions can be combined in the same individual ^ ; for example, the war- rior may be a husbandman, or an artisan ; or again, the coun- sellor a judge. And all claim to possess political ability, and 1 Or, ' Different functions appear to be often combined,' etc. Varieties of Democracy lyf think that they are quite competent to fill most offices. But IV. 4. the same persons cannot be rich and poor at the same time. ' For this reason the rich and the poor are regarded in an 19 especial sense as parts of a state. Again, because the rich are generally few in number, while the poor are many, they appear to be antagonistic, and as the one or the other prevails they form the government. Hence arises the common opinion that there are two kinds of government — democracy and oligarchy. I have already explained -^ that there are many differences 20 of constitutions, and to what causes the variety is due. Let me now show that there are different forms both of democracy and oligarchy, as will indeed be evident from what has pre- ceded. For both in the common people and in the notables 21 various classes are included ; of the common people, one class are husbandmen, another artisans ; another traders, who are employed in buying and selling ; another are the seafaring class, whether engaged in war or in trade, as ferrymen or as fishermen. (In many places any one of these classes forms quite a large population ; for example, fishermen at Tarentum and Byzantium, crews of triremes at Athens, merchant sea- men at Aegina and Chios, ferrymen at Tenedos.) To the classes already mentioned may be added day-labourers, and those who, owing to their needy circumstances, have no leisure, or those who are not free of birth on both sides ; and there may be other classes as well. The notables again may 22 be divided according to their wealth, biith, virtue, education, and similar differences. Of forms of democracy first comes that which is said to^ 1 JDC based strictly on equality. In such a democracy the law^ *** ^ Cp. iii. c. 6. ^> \^6 Extreme Democracy IV. 4|says that it is just for nobody to be poor, and for nobody to I be rich ^ ; and that neither should be masters, but both equal. 23 For if Hberty and equality, as is thought by some, are chiefly to be found in democracy, they will be best attained when all persons alike share in the government to the utmost. And since the people are the majority, and the opinion of the majority is decisive, such a government must necessarily be 24 a democracy. Here then is one sort of democracy. There : is another in which the magistrates are elected according to I a certain property qualification, but a low one ; he who has !the required amount of propeity has a share in the govern- 1292 )i ment, but he who loses his propeity loses his rights. Another kind is that in which all the citizens who are under no dis- qualification share in the government, but still the law is 25 supreme. In another, everybody, if he be only a citizen, is admitted to the government, but the law is supreme as before. A fifth form of democracy, in other respects the same, is that in which, not the law, but the multitude, have the supreme 26 power, and supersede the law by their decrees. This is a state of affairs brought about by the demagogues. For in democracies which are subject to the law the best citizens hold the first place, and there are no demagogues ; but where the laws are not supreme, there demagogues spring up. For the people becomes a monarch, and is many in one ; and the many have the power in their hands, not as individuals, but 27 collectively. Homer says that, 'it is not good to have a rule ^ Or, reading apxeiv with Victorius, * that the poor should no more govern than the rich.' The emenda'ion is not absolutely necessary, though supported by vi. 2. § 9, taov yap to jxtjOiv fidWov apxnv tovs dnopovs fj Tovs evirupovs l^rjol Kvpiovs elvai fiovovs aWa ndyras i^ laov icar apiQixov. Extreme Democracy if 7 of many' *, but whether he means this corporate rule, or the IV. 4 rule of many individuals, is uncertain. And the people, who ' is now a monarch, and no longer under the control of law, seeks to exercise monarchical sway, and grows into a despot ; the flatterer is held in honour ; this sort of democracy being relatively to other democracies what tyranny is to other forms of monarchy. The spirit of both is the same, and they alike '^8 exercise a despotic mle over the better citizens. The decrees of the demos correspond to the edicts of the tyrant ; and the demagogue is to the one what tlie flatterer is to the other. Both have great power — the flatterer with the tyrant, the demagogue with democracies of the kind which we are i describing. The demagogues make the decrees of the people 29 override the laws, and refer all things to the popular assembly. And therefore they grow great, because the people have all things in their hands, and they hold in their hands the votes of the people, who are too ready to listen to them. Further, 30 those who have any complaint to bring against the magis- trates say, ' let the people be judges ' ; the people are too happy to accept the invitation ; and so the authority of every office is undermined. Such a democracy is fairly open to the J objection that it is not a constitution at all ; for where thel laws have no authority, there is no constitution. The law pi ought to be supreme over all, and the magistracies and the government should judge only of particulars. So that if democracy be a real form of government, the sort of constitu- tion in which all things are regulated by decrees is clearly not a democracy in the true sense of the word, for decrees relate only to particulars ^ ' II. ii. 204. 9 Cp. N. Eih. V. 10. § 7. 1 5" 8 Varieties of Oligarchy IV. (5) These then are the different kinds of democracies. Of oligarchies, too, there are different kinds — one where the , property qualification for ofKce is so high that the poor, although they form the majority, have no share in the govern- ment, yet he who acquires a qualification may obtain a share. 1292 b Another sort is when there is a qualification for ofhce, but a high one, and the vacancies in the governing body are filled by co-optation. If the election is made out of all the qualified persons, a constitution of this kind inclines to an aristocracy, 2 if out of a privileged class, to an oligarchy. Another sort of oligarchy is when the son succeeds the father. There is a fourth form, likewise hereditary, in which the magistrates are supreme and not the law. Among oligarchies this is ' what tyranny is among monarchies, and the last-mentioned form of democracy among democracies ; and in fact this sort of oligarchy receives the name of a dynasty (or rule of powerful families). 3 These are the different sorts of oligarchies and democra- cies. It should however be remembered that in many states ^ the constitution which is established by law, although not democratic, owing to the character and habits of the people, may be administered democratically, and conversely in other states the established constitution may incline to democracy, 4 but may be administered in an oligarchical spirit. This most often happens after a revolution : for governments do not change at once ; at first the dominant party are content with encroaching a little upon their opponents. The laws which existed previously continue in force, but the authors of the revolution have the power in their hands. Q From what has been already said we may safely infer that Cp. V. I. § 8. Stages of Democracy i yp there are so many different kinds of democracies and of IV. 6 oligarchies. For it is evident that either all the classes whom '^ we mentioned must share in the government, or some only and not others. When the class of husbandmen and of those a i who possess moderate fortunes have the supreme power, the government is administered according to law. For the citi- zens being compelled to live by their labour have no leisure ; and so they set up the authority of the law, and attend assemblies only when necessary. Since they all obtain a 3 shaie in the government when they have acquired the quali- fication which is fixed by the law, nobody is excluded — the absolute exclusion of any class would be a step towards oligarchy. But leisure cannot be provided for them unless there are revenues to support them. This is one sort of democracy, and these are the causes which give birth to it. Another kind is based on the mode of election, ^ which naturally comes next in order ^ ; in this, every one to whose birth there is no objection is eligible, and may share in the government if he can find leisure. And in such a democracy 4 the supreme power is vested in the laws, because the state has no means of paying the citizens. K. third kind is when all 3 , freemen have a right to share in the government, but do not actually share, for the reason which has been already given ; -_ so that in this form again the law must rule. A fourth kind 5 >; ^Jr //jf.t^, i of democracy is that which comes latest in the history of 1293 a /^ /jf g . states. In our own day, when cities have far outgrown their original size, and their revenues have increased, all the citizens have a place in the government, through the great prepon- derance of their numbers ; and they all, including the poor who receive pay, and therefore have leisure to exercise their ^ Or, ' which is proper to it.' I (S'o Stages of Oligarchy IV. 6 liglits, share in the administration. Indeed, when they are 6 paid, the common people have the most leisure, for they are not hindered by the care of their property, which often fetters the rich, who are thereby prevented from taking part in the assembly or in the courts, and so the state is governed by the 7 poor, who are a majority, and not by the laws. So many kinds of democracies there are, and they grow out of these necessary causes. Of oligarchies, one form is that in which the majority of the citizens have some property, but not very much ; and this is the first form, which allows to any one who obtains the 8 required amount the right of sharing in the goveinment. The sharers in the government being a numerous body, it follows ^ I that the law must govern, and not individuals. For in pro- portion as they are further removed from a monarchical form of government, and in respect of property have neither so much as to be able to live without attending to business, nor so little as to need state support, they must admit the rule of law 9 and not claim to rule themselves. But if the men of property •^ ' in the state are fewer than in the former case, and own more property, there arises a second form of oligarchy. For the stronger they are, the more power they claim, and having this object in view, they themselves select those of the other classes who are to be admitted to the government ; but, not ] being as yet strong enough to rule without the law, they make lolthe law represent their wishes. When this power is inten- sified by a further diminution of their numbers and increase of their property, there arises a third and further stage of yj > oligarchy, in which the governing class keep the offices in their own hands, and the law ordains that the son shall II succeed the father. When, again, the rulers have great Aristocracy i the Pure and the Mixed 16 1 wealth and numerous friends, this sort of dynastia or family IV. 6 despotism approaches a monarchy; individuals rule and not "", the law. This is the fourth sort of oligarchy, and is analogous to the last sort of democracy. There are still two forms besides democracy and oligarchy; 1 Cf- Bli ^. ^^-o one of them is universally recognized and included among the ' rv-' 7' four principal forms of government, which are said to be (i) monarchy, (2) oligarchy, (3) democracy, and (4) the so- called aristocracy or government of the best. But there is also a fifth, which retains the generic name of polity or constitu- tional government ; this is not common, and therefore has not been noticed by writers who attempt to enumerate the dif- ferent kinds of government ; like Plato in his books about the 1293 b state, they recognize four only. The term 'aristocracy' 2 Cj:'^- is rightly applied to the form of government which is de- scribed in the first part of our treatise : for that only can be rightly called aristocracy [the government of the best] which is a government formed of the best men absolutely, and not merely of men who are good when tried by any given standard. In the perfect state the good man is absolutely the ^ same as the good citizen ; whereas in other states the good I citizen is only good relatively to his own form of govern- I ment. But there are some states differing from oligarchies 3 and also differing from the so-called polity or constitu- tional government ; these are termed aristocracies, and in them magistrates are certainly chosen, both according to their wealth and according to their merit. Such a form of govern- ment is not the same with the two just now mentioned, and is termed an aristocracy. For indeed in states which do not 4 /OfH make virtue the aim of the community, men of merit and reputation for virtue may be found. And so where a govern- DAVIS M i62 Mixed Co?istitutions IV. 7 ment has regard to wealth, virtue, and numbers, as at Car- thage •'j that is aristocracy ; and also where it has regard only to two out of the three, as at Lacedaemon, to virtue and numbers, and the two principles of democracy and virtue 5 temper each other. There are these two forms of aristocracy in addition to the first and perfect state, and there is a third form, viz. the polities which incline towards oligarchy. 8 I have yet to speak of the so-callednolity and of tyranny. I put them in this order, not because a polity or constitutional government is to be regarded as a perversion any more than the above-mentioned aristocracies. The truth is, that they all fall short of the most perfect form of government, and so they are reckoned among perversions, and other forms {sc. the really perverted forms) are perversions of these, as I 2 said before *. Last of all I will speak of tyranny, which I place last in the series because I am enquiring into the constitutions of states, and this is the very reverse of a constitution. Having explained why I have adopted this order, I will proceed to consider constitutional government ; of which the nature will be clearer now that oligarchy and democracy Z have been defined. For polity or constitutional government f may be described generally as a fusion of oligarchy and I democracy ; but the term is usually applied to those forms of government which incline towards democracy, and the term aristocracy to those which incline towards oligarchy, because birth and education are commonly the accompani- 4 ments of wealth. Moreover, the rich already possess the external advantages the want of which is a temptation to crime, and hence they are called noblemen and gentlemen. > Cp. ii, II. §§ 6-IO, * Cp. iii. 7. Mixed Constitutions 167^ And inasmuch as aiistocracy seeks to give predominance to IV. 8 the best of the citizens, people say also of oligarchies that they are composed of noblemen and gentlemen. No\vl2D4a it appears to be an impossible thing that the state which 5 is governed by the best citizens should be ill-governed ^, 'and equally impossible that the state which is ill-governed should be governed by the best. But we must remember that good laws, if they are not obeyed, do not constitute good govern- ■/ ment. For there are two parts of good government ; one 6 is the actual obedience of citizens to the laws, the other I £art is the goodness of the laws which they obey ; they 1 may obey bad laws as well as good. And there may be a fuither subdivision ; they may obey either the best laws which are attainable to them, or the best absolutely. The distribution of offices according to merit is a special." characteristic of aristocracy, for the principle of an aristocracy! is virtue, as wealth is of an oligarchy, and freedom of a democracy. In all of them there of course exists the right of the majority, and whatever seems good to the majority of those who share in the government has authority. Generally, s however, a state of this kind is called a constitutional govern- ment [not an aristocracy], for the fusion goes no further than the attempt to unite the freedom of the poor and the >c wealth of the rich, who commonly take the place of the noble. And as there are three grounds on which men claim 9 an equal share in the government— freedom, wealth, and virtue (for the fourth or good birth is the result of the two last, K being only ancient wealth and virtue) — it is clear that the admixture of the two elements, that is to say, of the richi and poor, is to be called a polity or constitutional government ; ^ Omitting dAAa irovrjpoKpaToviJLivrjv. M 2 I (5^4 Aristocracy and Polity IV. 8 and the union of the three is to be called aristocracy or the government of the best, and more than any other form of government, except the true and ideal, has a right to this name. lo Thus far I have described the different forms of states which exist besides monarchy, democracy, and oligarchy, and what they are, and in what aristocracies differ from one another, and polities from aristocracies — that the two latter are not very unlike is obvious. 9 Next we have to consider how by the side of oligarchy and democracy the so-called polity or constitutional govern- ment springs up, and how it should be organized. The nature of it will be at once understood from a comparison of oligarchy and democracy ; we must ascertain their different characteristics, and taking a portion from each, put the two 2 together, like the parts of an indenture. Now there are three modes in which fusions of government may be effected. The nature of the fusion will be made intelligible by an example of the manner in which different governments legislate, say con- cerning the administration of justice. In oligarchies they impose a fine on the rich if they do not serve as judges, and to the poor they give no pay ; but in democracies they give 3 pay to the poor and do not fine the rich. Now {j^ tiie union of these two modes ^ is a common or middle term between 1294 b them, and is therefore characteristic of a constitutional government, for it is a combination of both. This is one mode of uniting the two elements. Or {2,\ a mean may be taken between the enactments of the two : thus democracies require no property qualification, or only a small one, from members of the assembly, oligarchies a high one; here 1 Cp. c. 13. § 6. Polity 16^ neither of these is the common term, but a mean between them. IV. 9 (3) There is a third mode, in which something is borrowed 4 from the oHgarchical and something from the democratical principle. For example, the appointment of magistrates by^ jot is democratical, and the election of them oligarchical ;| democratical again when there is no property qualification, oligarchical when there is. In the aristocratical or constitu-,5 tional state, one element will be taken from each — from oli-f garchy the mode of electing to offices, from democracy thej ^sregard of qualification. Such are the various modes of 6 combination. There is a true union of oligarchy and democracy when the same state may be termed either a democracy or an oligarchy ; those who use both names evidently feel that the fusion is complete. Such a fusion there is also in the mean ; for both extremes appear in it. The Lacedaemonian constitution, 7 ■* kf't^° jf- ^ for example, is often described as a democracy, because it has many democratical features. In the first place the youth .'- / receive a democratical education. For the sons of the poor are brought up with the sons of the rich, who are educated in such a manner as to make it possible for the sons of the poor to be educated like them. A similar equality prevails 8 t< >• in the following period of life, and when the citizens are grown up to manhood the same rule is observed ; there is no distinction between the rich and poor. In like manner ^ they all have the same food at their public tables, and the rich wear only such clothing as any poor man can aiford. Again, the people elect to one of the two greatest 9 (N . a , //■/ offices of states, and in the other they share ^ ; for they elect ** u 'the Senators and share in the Ephoralty. By others the ^ Cp. ii. 9. § 21. 1 66 Tyranny IV. 9 Spartan constitution is said to be an oligarchy, because it has many oligarchical elements. That all offices are filled |. by election and none by lot, is one of these oligarchical characteristics ; that the power of inflicting death or banish- 2, , ment rests with a few persons is another ; and there are lo others. In a well attempered polity there should appear to be both elements and yet neither ; also the government should rely on itself, and not on foreign aid, nor on the good will of a majority of foreign states — they might be equally well- disposed when there is a vicious form of government — but on the general willingness of all classes in the state to maintain the constitution. Enough of the manner in which a constitutional government, and in which the so-called aristocracies ought to be framed. 10 Of the nature of tyranny I have still to speak, in order that It may have its place m our enquiry, since even tyranny is pdM^ CiiJil reckoned by us to be a form of government, although there is l^'h) o6~^ not much to be said about it. I have already in the former part of this treatise ^ discussed royalty or kingship according to the most usual meaning of the term, and considered whether it is or is not advantageous to states, and what kind of royalty should be established, and whence, and how it arises. 2 When speaking of royalty we also spoke of two forms of tyranny, which are both according to law, and therefore easily pass into royalty. Among Barbarians there are elected ^ monarchs who exercise a despotic power; despotic rulers were also elected in ancient Hellas, called Aesymnetes or 3 dictators. These monarchies, when compared with one another, exhibit certain differences. And they are, as I * iii. 14-17. Polity 167 said before, royal, in so far as the monarch rules accord- IV. 10 ing to law and over willing subjects ; but they are tyrannical in so far as he is despotic and rules according to his own fancy. There is also a third kind of tyranny, which is the most typical form, and is the counterpart of the perfect monarchy. This tyranny is just that arbitrary power of an 4 individual which is responsible to no one, and governs all ' alike, whether equals or betters, with a view to its own advantage, not to that of its subjects, and therefore against their will. No freeman, if he can escape from it, will endure such a government. The kinds of tyranny are such and so many, and for the reasons which I have given. We have now to enquire what is the best constitution 11 for most states, and the best life for most men, neither I assuming a standard of virtue which is above ordinary persons, nor an education which is exceptionally favoured by nature and circumstances, nor yet an ideal state which is an aspiration only, but having regard to the life in which the majority are able to share, and to the form of government which states in general can attain. As to those aristocracies, as they are 2 called, of which we were just now speaking, they either lie beyond the possibilities of the greater number of states,^ or they approximate to the so-called constitutional govern- ment, and therefore need no separate discussion. And in fact the conclusion at which we arrive respecting all these forms rests upon the same grounds. For if it has been truly 3 said in the Ethics ^ that the happy life is the life according to unimpeded virtue, and that virtue is a mean, then the life which is in a mean, and in a mean attainable by every 1 N. Eth. vii. 13. § 2. 1(58 The T{ule of the Isliddle Class IV. 11 one, must be the best. And the same criteria of virtue 1295 b and vice apply both to cities and to constitutions ; for the constitution is in a figure the life of the city ^. 4 Now in all states there are three elements ; one class is very rich, another very poor, and a third in a mean. It is admitted that moderation and the mean are best, and there- fore it will clearly be best to possess the gifts of fortune in moderation ; for in that condition of life men are most 5 ready to listen to reason. But he who greatly excels in beauty, strength, birth or wealth, or on the other hand who is very poor, or very weak, or very much disgraced, finds it , difficult to follow reason ^. Of these two the one sort grow into violent and great criminals, the others into rogues and petty rascals. And two sorts of offences correspond to them', the one committed from violence, the other from roguery. The petty rogues are disinclined to hold office, whether military or civil, and their aversion to these two duties is •^ as great an injury to the state as their tendency to crime. 6 Again, those who have too much of the goods of fortune, 1 strength, wealth, friends, and the like, are neither willing [nor able to submit to authority. The evil begins at home: for when they are boys, by reason of the luxury in which they are brought up *, they never learn, even at school, the habit of obedience. On the other hand, the very poor, who 7 are in the opposite extreme, are too degraded. So that the one class cannot obey, and can only rule despotically ; the other knows not how to command and must be mled like slaves. Thus arises a city, not of freemen, but of masters and slaves, the one despising, the other envying ; and nothing 1 Cp. iii. 3. §§ 7, 8. = Cp. PI. Rep. iv. 421 c, D ff. ^ Laws, viii 831 E. * Cp. v. 9. § 13. The T^ile of the Middle Class 1^9 can be more fatal to friendship and good fellowship in states IV. 11 than this : for good fellowship tends to friendship ; when men are at enmity with one another, they would rather not even share the same path. But a city ought to be composed, as far 8 as possible, of equals and similars ; and these are generally the middle classes. Wherefore the city which is composed I of middle-class citizens is necessarily best governed ; they I are, as we say, the natural elements of a state. And this is the class of citizens which is most secure in a state, for they do not, like the poor, covet their neighbours' goods ; nor do 9 others covet theirs, as the poor covet the goods of the rich ; and as they neither plot against others, nor are themselves plotted against, they pass through life safely. Wisely then did Phocylides pray — ' Many things are best in the mean ; I desire to be of a middle condition in my city.' Thus it is manifest that the best political community is lo formed by citizens of the middle class, and that those states are likely to be well-administered, in which the middle class \ is large, and larger if possible than both the other classes, or at any rate than either singly ; for the addition of the middle class turns the scale, and prevents either of the extremes from being dominant. Great then is the good ii fortune of a state in which the citizens have a moderate and sufficient property ; for where some possess much, and the 1296 a others nothing, there may arise an extreme democracy, or a pure oligarchy ; or a tyranny may grow out of either extreme — either out of the most rampant democracy, or out of an oligarchy ; but it is not so likely to arise out of a middle and nearly equal condition. I will explain the reason of this 13 17 o The Middle Class is rarely Supreme IV. 11 hereafter, when I speak of the revolutions of states ■'. The mean condition of states is clearly best, for no other is free ■from faction; and where the middle class is large, there 13 are least likely to be factions and dissensions. For a similar reason large states are less liable to faction than small ones, because in them the middle class is large ; whereas in small states it is easy to divide all the citizens into two classes who are either rich or poor, and to leave nothing in the middle. 14 And democracies are safer ^ and more permanent than oligarchies, because they have a middle class which is more numerous and has a greater share in the government ; for when there is no middle class, and the poor greatly exceed in number, troubles arise, and the state soon comes to an 15 end. A proof of the superiority of the middle class is that the best legislators have been of a middle condi- tion ; for example, Solon, as his own verses testify ; and Lycurgus, for he was not a king ; and Charondas, and almost all legislators. 16 These considerations will help us to understand why most governments are either democratical or oligarchical. The reason is that the middle class is seldom numerous in them, tI and whichever party, whether the rich or the common people, transgresses the mean and predominates, draws the govern- ment to itself, and thus arises either oligarchy or democracy. 17 There is another reason — the poor and the rich quarrel with one another, and whichever side gets the better, instead of establishing a just or popular government, regards political supremacy as the prize of victory, and the one party sets up 18 a democracy and the other an oligarchy. Both the parties which had the supremacy in Hellas looked only to the 1 Cp. Bk. y. » Cp. V. I. § 15 ; 7. § 6. The Goodwill of the Stronger 171 interest of their own form of government, and established in IV. 11 j states, the one, democracies, and the other, oligarchies ; they 'thought of their own advantage, of the public not at all. For 19 these reasons the middle form of government has rarely, if ever, existed, and among a very few only. One man alone of all who ever ruled in Hellas was induced to give this middle constitution to states. But it has now become a habit among 1296 b the citizens of states, not even to care about equality ; all men are seeking for dominion, or, if conquered, are willing to submit. What then is the best form of government, and what makes 20 it the best, is evident ; and of other states, since we say that there are many kinds of democracy and many of oligarchy, it is not difficult to see which has the first and which the second or any other place in the order of excellence, now that we have determined which is the best. For that which 21 is nearest to the best must of necessity be better, and that which is furthest from it worse, if we are judging absolutely and not relatively to given conditions : I say ' relatively to given conditions,' since a particular government may be preferable for some, but another form may be better for others. We have now to consider what and what kind of govern- 12 ment is suitable to what and what kind of men. I may begin by assuming, as a general principle common to all govern- ments, that the portion of the state which desires permanence ought to be stronger than that which desires the reverse. Now every city is composed of quality and quantity. By"^ quality I mean fieedom, wealth, education, good birth, and by 1 quantity, superiority of numbers. Quality may exist in one of>2 the classes which make up the state, and quantity in the 172 The Goodwill of the Stronger IV. 12 other. For example, the meanly-born may be more in number than the well-born, or the poor than the rich, yet they may not so much exceed in quantity as they fall short in 3 quality ; and therefore there must be a comparison of quantity and quality. Where the number of the poor is more than j proportioned to the wealth of the rich, there will naturally be ' a democracy, varying in form with the sort of people who compose it in each case. If, for example, the husbandmen exceed in number, the first form of democracy will then arise ; if the artisans and labouring class, the last ; and so with the intermediate forms. But wh'ere the rich and the notables exceed in quality more than they fall short in quantity, there ^oligarchy arises, similarly assuming various forms according to the kind of superiority possessed by the oligarchs. 4 The legislator should always include the middle class in his government; if he makes his laws oligarchical, to the middle class let him look; if he makes them democratical, he should equally by his laws try ^ to attach this class to ^ the state ^. There only can the government ever be stable 1297 4 where the middle class exceeds one or both of the others, and i in that case there will be no fear that the rich will unite with ' the poor against the mlers. For neither of them will ever be willing to serve the other, and if they look for some form of government more suitable to both, they will find nope better than this, for the rich and the poor will never consent to rule in turn, because they mistrust one another. The arbiter is always the one ti'usted, and he who is in the middle is an 6 arbiter. The more perfect the admixture of the political elements, the more lasting will be the state. Many even of * Or, if TTpoaa-yiaOai can govern tois vo/xoiS, ' to win this class over to his laws.' .^ The Policy of Oligarchies 173 those who desire to form aristocratical governments make IV. 12 a mistake, not only in giving too much power to the rich, but in attempting to overreach the people. There comes a time when out of a false good there arises a true evil, since the encroachments of the rich are more destructive to the state than those of the people. The devices by which oligarchies deceive the people are 13 ^jj^ in number; they relate to (l) the assembly; (2) the magistracies; (3) the courts of law ; (4) the use of arms ; (5) gymnastic exercises. (l) The assemblies are thrown open to all, but either the rich only are fined for non- attendance, or a much larger fine is inflicted upon them. (2) As to the magistracies, those who are qualified by 3 property cannot decline office upon oath, but the poor may. ' (3) In the law-courts the rich, and the rich only, are fined if they do not serve, the poor are let off with impunity, or, as in the laws of Charondas, a large fine is inflicted on the \., rich, and a smaller one on the poor. In some states all ^ citizens who have registered themselves are allowed to attend the assembly and to try causes ; but if after registration they do not attend in the assembly or at the courts, heavy fines are imposed upon them. The intention is that through fear of the fines they may avoid registering themselves, and then they cannot sit in the law-courts or in the assembly. (4) Concerning the possession of arms, and (5) gymnastic 4 exercises, they legislate in a similar spirit. For the poor are not obliged to have arms, but the rich are fined for not having them ; and in like manner no penalty is inflicted on the poor . for non-attendance at the gymnasium, and consequently, having nothing to fear, they do not attend, whereas the rich , are liable to a fine, and therefore they take care to attend. \, 174 Military Basis of the Constitution IV. 13 These are the devices of oligarchical legislators, and 5 in democracies they have counter devices. They pay the poor for attending the assemblies and the law-courts, and they \6 inflict no penalty on the rich for non-attendance. It is obvious that he who would duly mix the two principles should combine the practice of both, and provide that the poor should be paid to attend, and the rich fined if they do not attend, for then all will take part ; if there is no such combina- 1297 b tion, power will be in the hands of one party only. The ? government should be confined to those who carry arms. As to the property qualification, no absolute rule can be laid down, but we must see what is the highest qualification sufficiently comprehensive to secure that the number of those who have the rights of citizens exceeds the number of those 8 excluded. Even if they have no share in office, the poor, provided only that they are not outraged or deprived of their property, will be quiet enough. But to secure gentle treatment for the poor is not an easy 9 thing, since a ruling class is not always humane. And in time of war the poor are apt to hesitate unless they are fed ; when >. fed, they are willing enough to fight. In some states the government is vested, not only in those who are actually serving, but also in those who have served ; among the Malians, for example, the governing body consisted of the latter, while the magistrates were chosen from those actually 10 on service. And the earliest government which existed among 1 'J9 f f^ the Hellenes, after the overthrow of the kingly power, grew up out of the warrior class, and was originally taken from the knights (for strength and superiority in war at that time depended on cavalry ^) ; indeed, without discipline, infantry ' Cp. iv. 3. § 3; vi. 7. § I. The Distribution of Political Power 17 f are useless, and In ancient times there was no military know- IV. 13 ledge or tactics, and therefore the strength of armies lay in their cavalry. But when cities increased and the heavy armed grew in strength, more had a share in the government j and this is the reason why the states, which we call con- n stitutional governments, have been hitherto called democracies. ! Ancient constitutions, as might be expected, were oligarchical and royal ; their population being small they had no consider- able middle class ; the people were weak in numbers and organization, and were therefore more contented to be governed. I have explained why there are various forms of govern- 12 ment, and why there are more than is generally supposed ; for democracy, as well as other constitutions, has more than one form : also what their differences are, and whence they arise, and what is the best form of government, speaking generally, and to wliom the various forms of government are best suited; all this has now been explained. Having thus gained an appropriate basis of discussion we 14 will proceed to speak of the points which follow next in order. We will consider the subject not only in general but with reference to particular states. All states have three elements, and the good law-giver has to regard what is expedient for each state. When they are well-ordered, the state is well-ordered, and as they differ from one another, constitutions differ. What is the element first (i) which 2 deliberates about public affairs; secondly (2) which is con- 1298a cerned with the magistrates and determines what they should be, over whom they should exercise authority, and what should be the mode of electing them; and thirdly (^ which 3 has judicial power ? i7<^ Forms of the Deliberative Power IV. 1^ The deliberative element has authority in matters of war land peace, in making and unmaking alliances ; it passes laws, (inflicts death, exile, confiscation, audits the accounts of fmagistrates. All these powers must be assigned either to all Hhe citizens or to some of them, for example, to one or more magistracies ; or different causes to different magistracies, or 4 some of them to all, and others of them only to some. That all things should be decided by all is characteristic of democracy ; this is the sort of equality which the people desire. But there are various ways in which all may share in the government ; they may deliberate, not all in one body, but by turns, as in the constitution of Telecles the Milesian. f- There, are other states in which the boards of magistrates meet and deliberate, but come into office by turns, and are elected out of the tribes and the very smallest divisions of the state, until every one has obtained ofhce in his turn. The citizens, on the other hand, are assembled only for I the purposes of legislation, and to consult about the con- j, stitution, and to hear the edicts of the magistrates. In another variety of democracy the citizens form one assembly, but meet only to elect magistrates, to pass laws, to advise ■J^about war and peace, and to make scrutinies. Other matters are referred severally to special magistrates, who are elected 2 6 bv vote or by lot out of all the citizens. Or arain, the citizens meet about election to ofhces and about scrutinies, and deliberate concerning war or alliances, while other matters are administered by the magistrates, who, as far as is possible, are elected by vote ^ I am speaking of those magistracies in A. 7 which special knowledge is required. A fourth form of democracy is when all the citizens meet to deliberate about » Cp. vi. 2. § 5. In Democracies and Olifrarchies 177 everything, and the magistrates decide nothing, but only make IV. 14 the preliminary enquiries ; and that is the way in which the i last and worst form of democracy, corresponding, as we maintain, to the close family oligarchy and to tyranny, is at present administered. All these modes are democratical. On the other hand, that some should deliberate about all is ^ oliigarchical. This again is a mode which, like the demo- 8 cratical, has many forms. When the deliberative class, be'ng ' i elected out of those who have a moderate qualification, are numei-ous and they respect and obey the law without alter- ing it, and any one who has the required qualification shares in the government, then, just because of this moderation, the oligarchy inclines towards polity. But when only selected in- 1298 b3 ■ dividuals and not the whole people share in the deliberations of the state, then, although, as in the former case, they observe i the law, the government is a pure oligarchy. Or, again, 5 3, when those who have the power of deliberation are self- elected, and son succeeds father, and they and not the laws are supreme — the government is of necessity oligarchical. Where, again, particular persons have authority in particular 10 matters — for example, when the whole people decide about peace and war and hold scrutinies, but the magistrates regulate everything else, and they are elected either by vote or by lot — there ^ the form of government is an aristocracy or polity ^. And if some questions are decided by magistrates elected by vote, and others by magistrates elected by lot, either absolutely or out of select candidates, or elected both by vote and by lot — these practices are partly characteristic of an 1 Reading with several of the IVTSS. apiffTOKparia rj TroXmia, and omitting niv. Or, wi;h Bekker's text, apiaroKparia jxlv ij ttoKituo., ' the government is an aristocracy.' DAVIS N 178 In Democracies and Oligarchies IV. 14 aristocratical government, and partly of a pure constitutional government. 1 1 These are the various forms of the deliberative body ; they correspond to the various forms of government. And the government of each state is administered according to one or 12 other of the principles which have been laid down. Now it is for the interest of democracy, according to the most prevalent notion of it (I am speaking of that extreme form of democracy, in which the people are supreme even over the laws), with a view to better deliberation to adopt the custom ; of oligarchies respecting courts of law. For in oligarchies the rich who are wanted to be judges are compelled to attend under pain of a fine, whereas in democracies the poor are paid to attend. And this practice of oligarchies should be adopted by democracies in their public assemblies, for they will advise better if they all deliberate together — the people 13 with the notables and the notables with the people. It is also a good plan that those who deliberate should be elected \ by vote or by lot in equal numbers out of the different 1 classes ; and that if the people greatly exceed in number those who have political training, pay should not be given to I all, but only to as many as would balance the number of the notables, or that the number in excess should be eliminated -T by lot. But in oligarchies either certain persons should be chosen out of the mass, or a class of officers should be appointed such as exist in some states, who are termed probuli and guardians of the law ; and the citizens should occupy themselves exclusively with matters on which these have previously deliberated ; for so the people will have a share in the deliberations of the state, but will not be able IS to disturb the principles of the constitution. Again, in The Executive 179 oligarchies either the people ought to accept the measures IV. 14 of the government, or not to pass anything contrary to them ; or, if all are allowed to share in counsel, the decision should rest with the magistrates. The opposite of what is done in constitutional governments should be the rule in oligarchies ; the veto of the majority should be final, their assent not final, but the proposal should be referred back to the magistrates. Whereas in constitutional governments they take the contrary i6 course ; the few have the negative not the affirmative power ; the affirmation of everything rests with the multitude. 1299 a These, then, are our conclusions respecting the deliberative, that is, the supreme element in states. Next we will proceed to consider the distribution of 15 ^ ^ offices ; this, too, being a part of politics concerning which /? / • many questions arise : — What shall their number be ? Over what shall they preside, and what shall be their duration ? Sometimes they last for six months, sometimes for less; sometimes they are annual, whilst in other cases offices are held for still longer periods. Shall they be for life or for a long term of years ; or, if for a short term only, shall the same persons hold them over and over again, or once only? Also about the appointment to them — from whom are they to be chosen, by whom, and how ? We should 2 first be in a position to say what are the possible varieties of them, and then we may proceed to determine which are suited to different forms of government. But what are to be included under the term ' offices ' i" That is a question not quite so easily answered. For a political community requires many officers ; and not every one who is chosen by vote or by lot is to be regarded as a ruler. In the first place there are the_jriestSj. who must be distinguished from political N 2 i8o What Constitutes an Office? IV. 15 officers ; masters of choruses and heralds, even ambassadors, scare elected by vote [but still they are not political officers]. Some duties of superintendence again are political, extending either to all the citizens in a single sphere of action, like the office of the general who superintends them when they are in the field, or to a section of them only, like the inspectorships of women or of youth. Other offices are concerned with household management, like that of the coi^n measurers who exist in many states and are elected officers. Tliere are also menial offices which the rich have executed by 4 their slaves. Speaking generally, they are to be called offices to which the duties are assigned of deliberating about certain measures and of judging and commanding, especially the last; for to command is the especial duty of a magistrate. But the question is not of any importance in practice ; no one has ever brought into court the meaning of the word, although such problems have a speculative interest. 5 What kinds of offices, and how many, are necessary to the existence of a state, and which, if not necessary, yet conduce to its well-being, are much more important considerations, 6 affecting all states, but more especially small ones. For in great states it is possible, and indeed necessary, that every office should have a special function ; where the citizens are numerous, many may hold office. And so it happens that vacancies occur in some offices only after long intervals, or the office is held once only ; and certainly every work is 1299 b_better done which receives of the sole ^, and not the divided, » ^u'TM'VM' .'^" 7 attention of the worker. But in small states it is necessary tiivi&i^* to combine many offices in a few hands ", since the small number of citizens does not admit of many holding office : — » Cp. ii, 2. § 6. ^ Cp. vi. 8. what Constitutes an Office ? 1 8 i for who will there be to succeed them ? And yet small IV, 15 states at times require the same offices and laws as large ones ; the difference is that the one want them often, the others only after long intervals. Hence theie is no reason why the care 8 of many offices should not be imposed on the same person, for they will not interfere with each other. When the population is small, offices should be like the spits which also serve to hold a lamp^ We must first ascertain how many magistrates are necessary in every state, and also how many '^ are not exactly necessary, but are nevertheless useful, and then there will be no difficulty in judging what offices can be combined in one. We should also know when local tribunals 9 are to have jurisdiction over many different matters, and when authority should be centralized: for example, should one person keep order in the market and another in some other place, or should the same person be responsible everywhere ? Again, should offices be divided according to the subjects with which they deal, or according to the persons with whom they deal : I mean to say, should one person see to good order in general, or one look after the boys, another after the women, and so on ? Further, under different constitutions, 10 should the magistrates be the same or different ? For example, in democracy, oligarchy, aristocracy, monarchy, should there be the same magistrates, although they are elected, not out of equal or similar classes of citizens, but differently under different constitutions — in aristocracies, for example, they are chosen from the educated, in oligarchies from the wealthy, and in democracies from the free — or are there different offices proper to different constitutions'^, and * Cp. Note on i. 2. § 3. * See note. I 82 The Executive under IV. 15 may the same be suitable to some, but unsuitable to others ? For in some states it may be convenient that the same office should have a more extensive, in other states a narrower 11 sphere. Special offices are peculiar to certain forms of government : — for example, [to oligarchies] that of probuli, which is not a democratic office, although a bule or council is. (There must be some body of men whose duty is to prepare measures for the people in order that they may not be diverted from their business ; when these are few in number, the state inclines to an oligarcliy : or rather the probuli must always be 12 few, and are therefore an oligarchical element. But when both institutions exist in a state, the probuli are a check on the council ; for the counsellor is a democratic element, but the probuli are oligarchical. Even the power of the council disappears when democracy has taken that extreme 1300 a form, in which the people themselves are always meeting and 13 deliberating about everything. This is the case when the members of the assembly are wealthy or receive pay ; for they have nothing to do and are always holding assemblies and deciding everything for themselves. A magistracy which controls the boys or the women, or any similar office, is suited to an aristocracy rather than to a democracy ; for how can the magistrates prevent the wives of the poor from going out of doors ? Neither is it an oligarchical office ; for the wives of the oligarchs are too fine to be controlled. 14 Enough of these matters. I will now enquire into the appointment of offices. There are three questions to be answered, and the combinations of answers give all possible differences : first, who appoints ? secondly, from whom ? and \, 15 thirdly, how? Each of these three may further differ in ig At ^ r '^^^^ ways: (i) All the citizens, or only some, appoint; Different Constitutions 183 (2) Either the magistrates are chosen out of all or out of IV. 15 some who are distinguished either by a property qualification, j or by birth, or merit, or for some special reason, as at Megara only those were eligible who had returned from exile and fought together against the democracy; (3) They may be_a2E2ilited_either by vote or by lot. Again, these several 16 modes may be combined ; I mean that some officers may be elected by some, others by all, and some again out of some, and others out of all, and some by vote and others by lot. Each of these differences admits of four variations. 17 (i) Either all may elect out of all by vote, or all out of 1 all by lot ; and either out of all collectively or by sections, as, ' for example, by tribes, and wards, and phratries, until all the citizens have been gone through ; or the citizens may be in all cases eligible indiscriminately, and in some cases they may be elected by vote, and in some by lot. Again, (2) if only 18 some appoint, they may appoint out of all by vote, or out of all by lot ; or out of some by vote, out of some by lot, and some offices may be appointed in one way and some in another; I mean if they are appointed by all they may be appointed partly by vote and partly by lot'. Thus there will, be twelve forms of appointment without including the twoj combinations in the mode of election. Of these varieties two/ 19 are democratic forms, namely, when the choice is made by all the people out of all by vote or by lot, or by both, that is to say, some by lot and some by vote. The cases in which they do not all appoint at one time, but some appoint out of all or out of some by vote or by lot or by both (I mean some by lot and some by vote), or some out of all and others out ^ i. e. partly out of all and partly out of some, and partly by vote and partly by lot (see infra c. 16. § 6). 184 The Executive IV. 15 of some both by lot and vote, are characteristic of a polity or 20 constitutional government. That some should be appointed out of all by vote or by lot or by both, is oligarchical, and still more oligarchical when some are elected from all and some 'from some. That some should be elected out of all and some out of some, or again some by vote and others by 1300 b lot, is characteristic of a constitutional government, which 21 inclines to an aristocracy. That some should be chosen out of some, and some taken by lot out of some, is oligarchical ^ though not equally oligarchical ^ ; oligarchical, too, is the appointment of some out of some in both ways, and of some out of all. But that all should elect by vote out of some is aristocratical. 22 These are the different ways of constituting magistrates, and in this manner officers correspond to different forms of government: — which are proper to which, or how they ought to be established, will be evident when we determine the nature of their powers ^ By powers I mean such power as a rhagistrate exercises over the revenue or in defence of the country ; for there are various kinds of power : the power of the general, for example, is not the same with that which regulates contracts in the market. ^ 16 Of the three parts of government, the judicial remains _D • to be considered, and this we shall divide on the same JudiCtait principle. There are three points on which the varieties of law-courts depend — the persons from whom they are appointed, the matters with which they are concerned, and the manner of their appointment. I mean, (l) are the judges taken from all, or from some only ? (2) how many kinds of ^ These words are bracketed by Bekker in both editions. ' Omitting Kai with some MSS. and the old translator. 7: I8y 9^r£cJU; J.: (f^UUjLi) OJ, tttT^le^ ^./UJiit l"^ uoH ^iOoo Different Alodes of Appointing Judges law-courts are there: (3) are the judges chosen by vote or IV by lot ? First, let me determine how many kinds of law-courts - ^' there are. They are eight in number : One is die court of audits or scrutinies ; a second takes cognizance of [ordinary] offences against the state; a third is concerned^ with treason io-tv (jtro^ against the government ; the fourth ^determines disputes re- ^P^HiHH_B?™^iS^' whetlier raised by magistrates or by private persons ; the fifth decides the more important civil cases ; the sixth tries cases of homicide, which are of various kinds, 3 (a) premeditated, (&) unpremeditated, (c) cases in which the guilt is confessed but the justice is disputed ; and there may be a fourth court (d) in which murderers who have fled from justice are tried after their return ; such as the Court of Phreatto is said to be at Athens. But cases of this sort rarely happen at all even in large cities. The different kinds of homicide may be tried either by the same or by different courts. (7) There are courts for strangers : — of these there 4 are two subdivisions, (a) for the settlement of their disputes with one another, (&) for the settlement of disputes between I 1 r them and the citizens. And besides all these there must be (8) courts for small suits about sums of a drachma up to five drachmae, or a little more, which have to be determined, but they do not require many judges. Nothing more need be said of these small suits, nor of the 5 courts for homicide and for strangers : — I would rather speak of political cases, which, when mismanaged, create division and disturbances in states. Now if all the citizens judge, in all the different cases which I have distinguished, they ma^ be appointed by vote _or_ by lot, or soraetiaies by lot and sometimes by vote. Or 3\ I 8 (5 Different Modes of appointing Judges IV. 16 when a certain class of causes are tried, the judges who de- ^cide them may be appointed, some by vote, and some by lot. 1301 a These then are the four modes of appointing judges from the 6 whole people, and there will be likewise four modes, if they are elected from a part only ; for they rnay be appointed from some by vote and judge in all causes ; or they may be ^ appointed from some by lot and judge in all causes ; or they may be elected in some cases by vote, and m some cases taken by lot, or some courts, even when judging the same causes, T- may be composed of members some appointed by vote and some by lot. These then are the ways in which the aforesaid judges may be appointed. 7 Once more, the modes of appointment may be combined, I mean, that some may be chosen out of the whole people, others out of some, some out of both ; for example, the same tribunal may be composed of some who were elected out of all, and of others who were elected out of some, either by vote or by lot or by both. 8 In how many forms law-courts can be established has now been considered. The first form, viz. that in which the judges are taken from all the citizens, and in which all ' • 1 causes are tried, is democratical ; the second, which is com- i posed of a few only who try all causes, oligarchical ; the J. ■■ \ third, in which some courts are taken from all classes, and some from certain classes only, aristocratical and constitu- BOOK V ^'fi^'^'n^auJf^''^ The design which we projDOsed to ourselves is now nearly V. 1 completed ^ Next in order follow the causes of revolution in states, how many, and of what nature they are ; what elements work ruin in particular states, and out of what, and into what they mostly change ; also what are the elements of preservation in states generally, or in a particular state, and by what means each state may be best preserved : these questions remain to be considered. In the first place we must assume as our starting-point 2 that in the many forms of government which have sprung up there has always been an acknowledgement of justice and^ proportionate equality, although mankind fail in attaining them, as indeed I have already explained ^. Denipcracy, 3 for example, arises out of the notion that those who are equal in any respect are equal in all respects ; because men | are equally free, they claim to be absolutely equal. Ohgaichy is based on the notion that those who are unequal in one respect are in all respects unequal ; being unequal, that is, in property, they suppose themselves to be unequal absolutely. The democrats think that as they are equal they ought to be 4 ^ Cp. iv. c. 2. * Reading Kal with the MSS. and Bekker's ist ed. • Cp. iii. 9. §§ 1-4. 1 88 T{evolutions : their Causes V. 1 equal in all things ; while the oligarchs, under the idea that they are unequal, claim too much, which is one form of 5 inequality. All these forms of government have a kind of > justice, but, tried by an absolute standard, they are faulty ; and, therefore, both parties, whenever their share in the government does not accord with their preconceived ideas, 6 stir up revolution. Those who excel in virtue have the best 1301 b right of all to rebel (for they alone can with reason be deemed absolutely unequal) ^, but then they are of all men the least 7 inclined to do so'^. There is also a superiority which is claimed by men of rank ; for they are thought noble because they spring from wealthy and virtuous ancestors ^. Here 8 then, so to speak, are opened the very springs and fountains > of revolution ; and hence arise two sorts of changes in govern- , ments ; the one affecting the constitution, when men seek to change from an existing form into some other, for example, from democracy into oligarchy, and from oligarchy into demo- cracy, or from either of them into constitutional government or aristocracy, and conversely ; the other not affecting the con- j2.. - stitution, when, without disturbing the form of government, whether oligarchy, or monarchy, or any other, they try to get 9 the administration into their own hands *. Further, there is a question of degree ; an oligarchy, for example, may become •^ * more or less oligarchical, and a democracy more or less demo- cratical ; and in like manner the characteristics of the other forms of government may be more or less strictly maintained. , , , ■ lo Or, the revolution may be directed against a portion of the I If ' ' " constitution only, e. g. the establishment or overthrow of j " a particular office : as at Sparta it is said that Lysander 1 Cp. iii. 13. § 25. 2 Cp. c. 4. § 12. 2 Cp. iv. 8. § 9. * Cp. iv. 5. § 3. The Desire of F quality 189 attempted to overthrow the monarchy, and king Pausanias^ V. 1 the ephoralty. At Epidamnus, too, the change was partial. For instead of phylarchs or heads of tribes, a council was appointed; but to this day the magistrates are the only 11 members of the ruling class who are compelled to go to the Heliaea when an election takes place, and the office of the single archon ^ [survives, which] is another oligarchical feature. Everywhere inequality is a cause of revolution, but an in- equality in which there is no proportion, for instance, a per- D , petual monarchy among equals; and alwaysjt^is .t.he.4gsii:e.of equality which rises in rebellion. Nov, equality is of two kinds, numerical and proportional ; la by the first I mean sameness or equality in number or size ; by the second, equality of ratios. For example, the excess of three over two is equal to the excess of two over one ; whereas four exceeds two in the same ratio in which two exceeds one, for two is the same part of four that one is of two, namely, the half. As I was saying before^, men agree 13 about justice in the abstract, that it is treating others according to their deserts, but there is a difference of opinion about the application of the principle ; some think that if they are equal in any respect they are equal absolutely, others that if they are unequal in any respect they are unequal in all. Hence there 14 are two principal forms of government, democracy and oli- crarchy ; for good birth and virtue are rare, but wealth and 1302 a numbers are more common. In what city shall we find a hundred persons of good birth and of virtue ? whereas the poor everywhere abound. That a state should be oidered, simply and wholly, according to either kind of equality, is not ' Cp. vii. 14. § 20. * Cp. iii. 16. § I. 3 Cp. § 2; iii. 9. §§ 1-4. ipo The Great Source of Involution V. 1 a good thing ; the proof is the fact that such forms of govern- 15 ment never last. They are originally based on a mistake, and, as they begin badly, cannot fail to end badly. The inference is that both kinds of equality should be employed ; numerical in some cases, and proportionate in others. t Still democracy appears to be safer and less liable to revo- lt lution than oligarchy '. For in oligarchies ^ there is the double ^ danger of the oligarchs falling out among themselves and also with the people ; but in democracies ^ there is only the danger of a quarrel with the oligarchs. No dissension worth men- tioning arises among the people themselves. And we may further remark that a government which is composed of the S middle class more nearly approximates to democracy than to oligarchy*, and is the safest of the imperfect forms of government. 2 In considering how dissensions and political revolutions arise, we must first of all ascertain the beginnings and causes of them which affect constitutions generally. They may be said to be three in number ; and we have now to give an out- line of each. We want to know (l) what is the feeling ? and (2) what are the motives of those who make them? 2 (3) whence arise political disturbances and quarrels ? The universal and chief cause of this revolutionary feeling has been already mentioned ; viz. the desire of equality, when men think that they are equal to others who have more than themselves; or, again, the desire of inequality and superiority, when con- ceiving themselves to be superior they think that they have 3 not more but the same or less than their inferiors ; pretensions which may and may not be just. Inferiors revolt in order 1 Cp. iv. II. § 14. 2 Cp. c. 6. ^ Cp. c. 5. * Omitting f\ before rSiv oAiywy. Involutions 191 that they may be equal, and equals that they may be superior. V. 2 Such is the state of mind which creates revolutions. The motives for making them are the desire of gain and honour, or the fear of dishonour and loss ; tTiF authors of them want to divert punishment or dishonour from themselves or their friends. The causes and reasons of these motives and dis- 4 positions which are excited in men, about the things which I have mentioned, viewed in one way, may be regarded as seven, and in another as more than seven. Two of them 5 have been already noticed ' ; but they act in a different manner, for men are excited against one another by the love of gain and honour — not, as in the case which I have just supposed, in order to obtain them for themselves, but at seeing 1302 b others, justly or unjustly, engrossing them. Other causes are 6 insolence, fear, love of superiority, contempt, disproportionate increase in some part of the state ; causes of another sort are election intrigues, carelessness, neglect about trifles, dissimi- larity of elements. What share insolence and avarice have in creating revolu- 3 tions, and how they work, is plain enough. When the magistrates are insolent and grasping they conspire against one another and also against the constitution from which they derive their power, making their gains either at the expense of individuals or of the public. It is evident, again, what an a influence hongur exerts and how it is a cause of revolution. Men who are themselves dishonoured and who see others obtaining honours rise in rebellion ; the honour or dishonour when un- deserved is unjust, and just when awarded according to merit. Again, superiority is a cause of revolution when one 3 or more persons have a power which is too much for the * Supra §§ 2, 3. 192 Causes of T^eyohitions V. 3 state and the power of the government ; this is a condition of affairs out of which there arises a monarchy, or a family oligarchy. And, therefore, in some places, as at Athens and Argos, they have recourse to ostracism ^ But how much better to provide from the first that there should be no such pre-eminent individuals instead of letting them come into existence and then finding a remedy. 4 Another cause of revolution is fear. Either men have committed wrong, and are afraid of punishment, or _they_are expecting to suffer wrong and are desirous of anticipating their enemy ^. Thus at Rhodes the notables conspired aoainst the people through fear of the suits that were brought 5 against them. Contempt is also a cause of insurrection and "^ revolution ; for example, in oligarchies — when those who have no share in the state are the majority, they revolt, because they think that they are the stronger. Or, again, in democracies, the rich despise the disorder and anarchy of the state ; at Thebes, for example, where, after the battle of Oenophyta, the bad administration of the democracy led to its ruin. At Megara the fall of the democracy was due to a defeat occasioned by disorder and anarchy. And at Syracuse the democracy was overthrown before the tyranny of Gelo arose ; at Rhodes before the insurrection. 6 Political revolutions also spring from a disproportionate I .^ increase in any part of the state. For as a body is made up of many members, and every member ought to grow in proportion ^, that symmetry may be preserved, but loses its nature if the foot be four cubits long and the rest of the 1303 a body two spans ; and, should the abnormal increase be one of 1 Cp. hi. 13- § 15- ' Cp. c. 5. § 2. 2 Cp. iii. 13. § 21. Occasions of Involutions 193 quality as well as of quantity, may even take the foim of V. 3 another animal : even so a state has many parts, of which some one may often grow imperceptibly ; for example, the number of poor in democracies and in constitutional states. >C. And this disproportion may sometimes happen by an accident, 7 as at Tarentum, from a defeat in which many of the notables were slain in a battle with the lapygians just after the Persian War, the constitutional government in consequence becoming a democracy ; or, as was the case at Argos, where after the losses inflicted in ' the Battle of the Seventh Day ' by Cleomenes the Lacedaemonian, the Argives were com- pelled to admit to citizenship some of their perioeci : and at Athens, when, after frequent defeats of their infantry in the times of the Peloponnesian War, the notables were reduced in number, because the soldiers had to be taken from the roll of citizens. Revolutions arise from this cause in 8 democracies as well as in other forms of government, but not to so great an extent. When the rich ^ grow numerous or properties increase, the form of government changes into an oligarchy or a government of families. Forms of government ,9 also change — sometimes even without revolution, owing to' election contests, as at Heraea (where, instead of electing'^ their magistrates, they took them by lot, because the electors were in the habit of choosing their own partisans) ; or owing to carelessness, when disloyal persons are allowed to find >^ their way into the highest offices, as at Oreum, where, upon the accession of Heracleodorus to office, the oligarchy was overthrown, and changed by him into a constitutional and democratical government. ^ Reading (virSpxv. O 194 Occasions of 'Revolutions V. 3 Again, the revolution may be accomplished by small 10 degrees ; I mean that a great change may sometimes slip into the constitution through neglect of a small matter ; at Ambracia, for instance, the qualification for office, small at first, was eventually reduced to nothing. For the Ambraciots thought that a small qualification was much the same as none at all. 1 1 Another cause of revolution is difference of races which do not at once acquire a common spirit ; for a state is not the growth of a day, neither is it a multitude brought together by accident. Hence the reception of strangers in colonies, either at the time of their foundation or afterwards, has generally produced revolution ; for example, the Achaeans who joined the Troezenians in the foundation of Sybaris, being the more numerous, afterwards expelled them ; hence 12 the curse fell upon Sybaris. At Thurii the Sybarites quarrelled with their fellow-colonists ; thinking that the land belonged to them, they wanted too much of it and were driven out. At Byzantium the new colonists were detected in a conspiracy, and were expelled by force of arms ; the people of Antissa, who had received the Chian exiles, fought with them, and drove them out ; and the Zancleans, after having received the Samians, were driven by them out of 13 their own city. The citizens of Apollonia on the Euxine, after the introduction of a fresh body of colonists, had a revolution ; the Syracusans, after the expulsion of their 1303 b tyrants, having admitted strangers and mercenaries to the rights of citizenship, quarrelled and came to blows ; the people of Amphipolis, having received Chalcidian colonists, were nearly all expelled by them. 14 Now, in oligarchies the masses make revolution undei the Occasions of 'Revolutions i 9 j- idea that they are unjustly treated, because, as I said before, V. 3 they are equals, and have not an equal share, and in democracies the notables revolt, because they are not equals, and yet have only an equal share. Again, the situation of cities is a cause of revolution when i^ the country is not naturally adapted to preserve the unity of the state. For example, the Chytrians at Clazomenae did not agree with the people of the island ; and the people of Colophon quarrelled with the Notians ; at Athens, too, the inhabitants of the Piraeus are more democratic than those who live in the city. For just as in war, the impediment of i6 a ditch, though ever so small, may break a regiment, so every cause of difference, however slight, makes a breach in a city. The greatest opposition is confessedly that of virtue and vice ; next comes that of wealth and poverty ; and there are other antagonistic elements, greater or less, of which one is this difference of place. In revolutions the occasions may be trifling, but greati4, t / interests are at stake. Trifles are most important when! P^^ '7 they concern the rulers, as was the case of old at Syracuse ; for the Syracusan constitution was once changed by a love- quarrel of two young men, who were in the government. The story is that while one of them was away from home 3 his beloved was gained over by his companion, and he to revenge himself seduced the other's wife. They then drew all the members of the ruling class into their quarrel and made a revolution. We learn from this story that we should 3 be on our guard against the beginnings of such evils, and should put an end to the quarrels of chiefs and mighty men. The mistake lies in the beginning — as the proverb says, ' Well begun is half done ' — so an error at the beginning, O 2 1^6 Occasions of 'Revolutions^ V. 4 though quite small, has the proportion of a half to the whole 4 matter. In general, when the notables quarrel, the whole city is involved, as happened in Hestiaea after the Persian War. _^ The occasion was the division of an inheritance ; one of two brothers refused to give an account of their father's property and the treasure which he had found : so the poorer of the two quarrelled with him and enlisted in liis cause the popular party, the other, who was very rich, the wealthy classes. 5 At Delphi, again, a quarrel about a marriage was the 1304 a beginning of all the troubles which followed. In this case the bridegroom, fancying some occurrence to be of evil omen, came to the bride, and went away without taking her. Whereupon her relations, thinking that they were insulted by him, put some of the sacred treasure [among his offerings] while he was sacrificing, and then slew him, pretending that 6 he had been robbing the temple. At Mitylene, too, a dis- pute about heiresses was the beginning of many misfortunes, and led to the war with the Athenians in which Paches took their city. A wealthy citizen, named Timophanes, left two daughters; Doxander, another citizen, wanted to obtain them for his sons, but he was rejected in his suit, whereupon he stirred up a revolution, and instigated the Athenians (of 7 whom he was proxenus) to interfere. A similar quarrel about an heiress arose at Phocis between Mnaseas the father of Mnason, and Euthycrates the father of Onomarchus ; this was the beginning of the Sacred War. A marriage-quarrel was also the cause of a change in the government of Epidamnus. A certain man bethrothed his daughter secretly to a person whose father, having been made a magistrate, fined the father of the girl, and the latter, stung by the insult, and the Marnier of Effecthig Them 197 conspired with the unenfranchised classes to overthrow the V. 4 state. Governments also change into oligarchy or into democracy 8 or into a constitutional government because the magistrates, or [ some other section of the state, increase in power or renown. Thus at Athens the reputation gained by the court of the Areopagus, in the Persian War, seemed to tighten the reins of government. On the other hand, the victory of Salamis^, which was gained by the common people who served in the fleet, and won for the Athenians the empire of the sea, strengthened the democracy. At Argos, the notables, 9 having distinguished themselves against the Lacedaemonians in the battle of Mantinea, attempted to put down the demo- cracy. At Syracuse, the people having been the chief , authors of the victory in the war with the Athenians, changed j the constitutional government into democracy. At Chalcis, the people, uniting with the notables, killed Phoxus the tyrant, and then seized the government. At Ambracia ^, the people, in like manner, having joined with the conspirators in expelling the tyrant Periander, transferred the government to themselves. And generally, it should be remembered thatiCo those who have secured power to the state, whether private ; citizens, or magistrates, or tribes, or any other part or section of the state, are apt to cause revolutions. For either ^ envy of their greatness draws others into rebellion, or they themselves, in their pride of superiority, are unwilling to remain on a level with others. I Revolutions break out when opposite parties, e.g. the rich r i land the poor, are equally balanced, and there is little or 1304b ^ Cp. ii. 12. § 5 ; viii. 6. § il. "^ Cp. supra c. 3. § 10, and infra c. 10. § 16. ^ (|./W)i<^ffc7?nrM^ 198 Occasions of Revolutions V. 4 nothing between them ; for, if either party were manifestly 1 2 superior, the other would not risk an attack upon them. And, for this reason, those who are eminent in virtue do not stir up insurrections, being always a minority. Such are the beginnings and causes of the disturbances and revolutions to which every form of government is liable. Revolutions are effected in two ways, by force and by fraud. Force may be applied either at the time of making the 13 revolution or afterwards. Fraud, again, is of two kinds ; for (i) sometimes the citizens are deceived into a change of 1 government, and. afterwards they are held in subjection against ' their will. This was what happened in the case of the Four Hundred, who deceived the people by telling them that the king would provide money for the war against the Lace- daemonians, and when the deception was over, still endeavoured to retain the government, (2) In other cases the people are persuaded at first, and afterwards, by a repetition of the persuasion, their goodwill and allegiance are retained. The revolutions which affect constitutions generally spring from the above-mentioned causes ^. 5 And now, taking each constitution separately, we must see what follows from the principles already laid down. Revolutions in democracies are generally caused by the in- >^X,'lAM//>^' ¥ {temperance of demagogues, who either in their private capacity v^ . , lay information against rich men until they compel them / to combine (for a common danger unites even the bitterest enemies), or coming forward in public they stir up the people against them. The truth of this remark is proved by a 2 variety of examples. At Cos the democracy was overthrown because wicked demagogues arose, and the notables combined. ' Cp. supra c. 2. § I. ^volutions in Democracies 199 At Rhodes the demagogues not only provided pay for the V. 5 multitude, but prevented them from making good to the trierarchs the sums which had been expended by them ; and they, in consequence of the suits which were brought against them, were compelled to combine and put down the democracy ^. The democracy at Heraclea was overthrown 3 shortly after the foundation of the colony by the injustice of the demagogues, which drove out the notables, who came back in a body and put an end to the democracy. Much in 4 the same manner the democracy at Megara ^ was overturned ; there the demagogues drove out many of the notables in order that they might be able to confiscate their property. At length the exiles, becoming numerous, returned, and engaging and defeating the people, established an oligarchy. The same 1305 a thing happened with the democracy of Cyme which was over- thrown by Thrasymachus. And we may observe that in most .S states the changes have been of this character. For sometimes the demagogues, in order to curry favour with the people,/ wrong the notables and so force them to combine ; — either they make a division of their property, or diminish their^ incomes by the imposition of public services, and sometimes they bring accusations against the rich that they may have their wealth to confiscate '. Of old, the demagogue was also a general, and then demo- 6 cracies changed into tyrannies. Most of the ancient tyrants I were originally demagogues *. They are not so now, but 7 they were then ; and the reason is that they were generals and not orators, for oratory had not yet come into fashion. Whereas in our day, when the art of rhetoric has made such 1 Cp. supra c. 3. § 4. ** Cp. c. 3. § 5, and iv, 15. § 15. 3 Cp. infra c. 8. § 20. * Cp. c. 10. § 4 ; Plato, Rep. viii. 565 D. 2 00 The Demagogue and the Tyrant V. 5 progress, the orators lead the people, but their ignorance of military matters prevents them from usurping power ; at any 8 rate instances to the contrary are few and slight. Formerly tyrannies were more common than they are now, because great power was often placed in the hands of individuals ; thus a tyranny arose at Miletus out of the office of the Pry- tanis, who had supreme authority in many important matters*. Moreover, in those days, when cities were not large, the people dwelt in the fields, busy at their work ; and their chiefs, 9 if they possessed any military talent, seized the opportunity, and winning the confidence of the masses by professing their hatred of the wealthy, they succeeded in obtaining the tyranny. Thus at Athens Peisistratus led a faction against the men of the plain ^, and Theagenes at Megara slaughtered the cattle of the wealthy, which he found by the river side where they 10 had put them to graze, Dionysius, again, was thought woithy of the tyranny because he denounced Daphnaeus and the rich ; his enmity to the notables won for him the confidence of the people. Changes also take place from the ancient to the latest form of democracy ; for where there is a popular elec- j tion of the magistrates and no property qualification, the aspirants for office get hold of the people, and contrive at 11 last even to set them above the laws. A more or less com- plete cure for this state of things is for the separate tribes, and not the whole jseople, to elect the magistrates. These are the principal causes of revolutions in demo- cracies. 6 There are two patent causes of revolutions in oligarchies [one coming from without, the other from within the govern- ment] : (l) First, when the oligarchs oppress the people, ^ Cp. infra c. 10. § 5. ' See Herod, i. 59. Involutions in Oligarchies 20 r for then anybody is good enough to be their champion, V. 6 especially if he be himself a member of the oligarchy, as 1305 b Lygdamis at Naxos, who afterwards came to be tyrant. JBut 2 revolutions which commence outside the governing class may be further subdivided. Sometimes, when the government is very exclusive, the revolution is brought about by persons of^ "^ the wealthy class who are excluded, as happened at Massalia and Istros and Heraclea, and other cities. Those who had 3 no share in the government created a disturbance, until first the elder brothers, and then the younger, were admitted ; for in some places father and son, in others elder and younger brothers, do not hold office together. At Massalia the oli- garchy became more like a constitutional government, but at Istros ended in a democracy, and at Heraclea was enlarged to 600. At Cnidos, again, the oligarchy underwent a con- 4 siderable change. For the notables fell out among themselves, because only a few shared in the government ; there existed among them the rule already mentioned, that father and son could not hold office together, and, if there were several brothers, only the eldest was admitted. The people took advantage of the quarrel, and choosing one of the notables to be their leader, attacked and conquered the oligarchs, who were divided, and division is always a source of weakness. The city of Erythrae, too, in old times was ruled, and ruled 5 well, by the Basilidae, but the people took offence at the narrowness of the oligarchy and changed the government. (2) Of internal causes of revolutions in oligarchies one is the personal rivalry of the oligarchs, which leads them to play the demagogue. Now, the oligarchical demagogue is of' two sorts : either (i) he practises upon the oligarchs them- selves (for, although the oligarchy are quite a small number. 4. 2 02 Their Causes External and Internal V. 6 there may be a demagogue among them, as at Athens the party of Charicles predominated among the Thirty, that of Phrynichus in the Four Hundred) ; or (2) the oligarchs may play the demagogue with the people. This was the case at Larissa, where the guardians of the citizens endeavoured to gain over the people because they were elected by them ; and such is the fate of all oligarchies in which the magistrates are elected, as at Abydos, not by the class to which they belong, but by the heavy-armed or by the people, although they may be required to have a high qualification, or to be members of 7 a political club ; or, again, where the law-courts are inde- pendent of the government, the oligarchs flatter the people in order to obtain a decision in their own favour, and so they change the constitution ; this happened at Heraclea in Pontus. Again, oligarchies change whenever any attempt is made to narrow them ; for then those who desire equal rights are com- 8 pelled to call in the people. Changes in the oligarchy also occur when the oligarchs waste their private property by < extravagant living ; for then they want to innovate, and 1306 a either try to make themselves tyrants, or install some one else in the tyranny, as Hipparinus did Dionysius at Syracuse, and as at Amphipolis^ a man named Cleotimus introduced Chal- cidian colonists, and when they arrived, stirred them up 9 against the rich. For a like reason in Aegina the person who carried on the negotiation with Chares endeavoured to revolutionize the state. Sometimes a party among the oli- garchs try to create a political change ; sometimes they rob the treasury, and then, either the other oligarchs quarrel with the thieves, as happened at Apollonia in Pontus, or they with the other oligarchs. But an oligarchy which is at unity 1 Cp. c. 3. § 13. 7' Oligarchy^ Dangers in Peace and War 203 with itself is not easily destroyed from within ; of this we V. may see an example at Pharsalus, for there, although the lo rulers are few in number, they govern a large city, because they have a good understanding among themselves. Oligarchies, again, are overthrown when another oligarchy is created within the original one, that is to say, wlien thejii whole governing body is small and yet they do not all share* in the highest offices. Thus at Elis the governing body was a small senate ; and vcjy few ever found their way into it, because, although in number ninety, the senators were elected for life and out of certain families in a manner similar to the Lacedaemonian elders. Oligarchy is liable to revolutions 12 alike in war and in peace ; in war because, not being able to trust the people, the oligarchs are compelled to hire mer- | o-, cenaries, and the general who is in command of them often ends in becoming a tyrant, as Timophanes did at Corinth ; or if there are more generals than one they make themselves into a company of tyrants ^ Sometimes the oligarchs, fearing this danger, give the people a share in the government because their services are necessary to them. And in time of peace, 13 - "i from mutual distrust, the two parties hand over the defence of the state to the army and to an arbiter between the two factions who often ends the master of both. This happened at Larissa when Simosand the Aleuadae had the government, and at Abydos in the days of Iphiades and the political clubs. Revolutions also arise out of marriages or lawsuits which lead 14 to the overthrow of one party among the oligarchs by another. "^ ♦ Of quarrels about marriages I have already mentioned '^ some instances ; another occurred at Eretria, where Diagoras over- turned the oligarchy of the knights because he had been ^ SwaffTfta. ^ Cp. c. 4. §§ 5-7. 1 k 204 Involutions in Oligarchies V. 6 wronged about a marriage. A revolution at Heraclea, and 15 another at Thebes, both arose out of decisions of law-courts upon a charge of adultery ; in both cases the punishment was just, but executed in the spirit of party, at Heraclea upon 1306 b Eurytion, and at Thebes upon Archias ; for their enemies were jealous of them and so had them pilloried in the :6 agora. Many oligarchies have been destroyed by some members of the ruling class taking offence at their excessive despotism; for example, the oligarchy at Cnidus and at Chios. Changes of constitutional governments, and also of oli- garchies which limit the office of counsellor, judge, or other magistrate to persons having a certain money qualification, *^* 17 often occur by accident. The qualification may have been originally fixed according to the circumstances of the time, in such a manner as to include in an oligarchy a few only, or in a constitutional government the middle class. But aftei a time of prosperity, whether arising from peace or some other good fortune, the same property becomes many times as large, and then everybody participates in every office ; this happens sometimes gradually and msensibly, and sometimes 1 8 quickly. These are the causes of changes and revolutions in oligarchies. We must remark generally, both of democracies and oli- I garchies, that they sometimes change, not into the opposite ' forms of government, but only into another variety of the ' y same class ; I mean to say, from those forms of democracy and oligarchy which are regulated by law into those which are arbitrary, and conversely. ;'4*.'&/'*v» /t 17, In aristocracies revolutions are stirred up when a few only (JfCt^fvt.\l^e4£i> {share in the honours of the state ; a cause which has been 'Revolutions in Oligarchies 205* already shown to affect oligarchies ; for an aristocracy is V. 7 a sort of oligarchy, and, like an oligarchy, is the government of a few, although the few are the virtuous and not the wealthy ; hence the two are often confounded. And revo- 2 lutions will be most likely to happen, and must happen, when 1 the majority of the people are high-spirited, and have a notion | '/ 1 that they are as good as their rulers. Thus at Lacedaemon the so-called Partheniae, who were the [illegitimate] sons of, the Spartan peers, attempted a revolution, and, being detected, ' were sent away to colonize Tarentum. Again, revolutions occur when great men who are at least of equal merit arel ^5, dishonoured by those higher in office, as Lysander was by' 3 the kings of Sparta : or, when a brave man is excluded from ^ the honours of the state, like Cinadon, who conspired against ' ' the Spartans under Agesilaus ; or, again, when some are very poor and others very rich, a state of society which is most K often the result of war, as at Lacedaemon in the days of the Messenian War ; this is proved from the poem of Tyrtaeus, 4 entitled ' Good Order' ; for he speaks of certain citizens who 1307a were ruined by the war and wanted to have a redistribution of the land. Again, revolutions arise when an individual who A is great, and might be greater, wants to rule alone, as at Lace- ^ daemon, Pausanias, who was general in the Persian War, or like Hanno at Carthage. Constitutional governments and aristocracies are commonly 5 overthrown owing to some deviation from justice in the con-j f ^ stitution itself; the cause of the downfall is, in the former, the ill-mingling of the two elements democracy and oligarchy ; in the latter, of the three elements, democracy, oligarchy, and virtue, but especially democracy and oligarchy. For to com- bine these is the endeavour of constitutional governments ; 10 6 I\evolutions in Aristocracies^ etc. 7 and most of the so-called aristocracies have a like aim ^, but 6 differ from polities by the addition of virtue ; hence some of them are more and some less permanent. Those which incline more to oligarchy are called aristocracies, and those which incline to democracy constitutional governments. And therefore the latter are the safer of the two ; for the greater the number, the greater the strength, and when men are equal 7 they are contented. But the rich, if the government gives them power, are apt to be insolent and avaricious ; and, in general, whichever way the constitution inclines, in that direc- tion it changes as either party gains strength, a constitutional government becoming a democracy, an aiistocracy, an oli- 8 garchy. But the process may be reversed, and aristocracy ^\ may change into democracy. This happens when the poor, under the idea that they are being wronged, force the consti- tution to take an opposite form. In like manner constitutional governments change into oligarchies. The only stable prin- ciple of government is equality according to proportion, and j for every man to enjoy his own. 9 What I have just mentioned actually happened at Thurii ^, where the qualification for office, though at first high, was reduced, and the magistrates increased in number. The notables had previously acquired the whole of the land contrary to law ; for the government tended to oligarchy, and they were able to encroach. But tlie people, who had been trained by war, soon got the better of the guards kept by the oligarchs, until those who had too much gave up their land. lo Again, since all aristocratical governments incline to oli- garchy, the notables are apt to be grasping; thus at Lacedae- mon, where property has passed into few hands ^, the notables 1 Cp. iv. c. 7. ^ Cp. c. 3. § 12. ^ Cp. ii. 9. § 14. T^evoluiions in Mixed Governments 207 can do too much as they like, and are allowed to marry whom v. 7 they please. The city of Locri was ruined by a marriage connexion with Dionysius, but such a thing could never have happened in a democracy, or in a well-balanced aristocracy. I have alieady remarked that in all states revolutions are^'n occasioned by trifles '. In aristocracies, above all, they are of 1307 d a gradual and imperceptible nature. The citizens begin by^, giving up some part of the constitution, and so with greater ease the government change something else which is a little more important, until they have undermined the whole fabric of the state. At Thurii there was a law that generals should 1 2 only be re-elected after an interval of five years, and some high-spirited young men who were popular with the soldiers of the guard, despising the magistrates and thinking that they would easily gain their purpose, wanted to abolish this law and . allow their generals to hold perpetual commands ; for they ( well knew that the people would be glad enough to elect them. Whereupon the magistrates who had charge of these matters, 13 and who are called councillors, at first determined to resist, but they afterwards consented, thinking that, if only this one law was changed, no further inroad would be made on the constitution. But other changes soon followed which they in vain attempted to oppose ; and the state passed into the hands of the revolutionists who established a dynastic oligaichy. All constitutions are overthrown either from within orfromji< without ; the latter, when there is some government close at I hand having an opposite interest, or at a distance, but powerful. This was exemplified in the old times of the Athenian and the Lacedaemonian supremacies ; the Athenians everywhere 4. § I. sr U 208 The Preservation of States V. 7 put down the oligarchies, and the Lacedaemonians the democracies ^. 1 have now explained what are the chief causes of revolu- tions and dissensions in states. 8 We have next to consider what means there are of pre- 'CiH 0] p'-3r//'' I serving states in general, and also in particular cases. In the '^lai'L ^''-'''^ place it is evident that if we know the causes which destroy states, we shall also know the causes which preserve them ; for opposites produce opposites, and destruction is the opposite of preservation ^. 2 In all well-attempered governments there is nothing which should be more jealously maintained than the spirit of obedience to law, more especially in small matters ; for 'transgression creeps in unperceived and at last ruins the state, just as the constant recurrence of small expenses in time eats 3 up a fortune. The change does not take place all at once, and therefore is not observed ; the mind is deceived, as in the fallacy which says that ' if each part is little, then the whole is little.' And this is true in one way, but not in another, for the whole and the all are not little, although they are made up of littles. 4 In the first place, then, men should guard against the beginning of change, and in the second place they should not a rely upon the political devices of which I have already spoken ^, invented only to deceive the people, for they are 5 proved by experience to be useless. Further we note that oligarchies as well as aristocracies may last, not from any inherent stability in such forms of government, but because the rulers are on good terms both with the unenfranchised and > Cp. iv. II. § 18. * Cp. Nic. Eth. v. i. § 4. » Cp. iv. 13. § I. Hoiv to avoid ^volution 209 with the governing classes, not maltreating any who are V. 8 excluded from the government, but introducing into it the leading spirits among them ^ They should never wrong the 3i ambitious in a matter of honour, or the common people in a matter of money ; and they should treat one another and their fellow-citizens in a spirit of equality. The equality 6 which the friends of democracy seek to establish for the multitude is not only just but likewise expedient among equals. Hence, if the governing class are numerous, many democratic institutions are useful ; for example, the restriction of the tenure of offices to six months, that all those who are of equal rank may share in them. Indeed, equals or peers when they are numerous become a kind of democracy, and therefore demagogues are very likely to arise among them, as I have *4-. already remarked ^ The short tenure of office prevents o'i"f 7//^ffv<< (k^ «i families ; it is not easy for a person to do any great harm Jf-L ^-nA&LU^ when his tenure of office is short, whereas long possession %^^^f,^{^ oS^ begets tyranny in oligarchies and democracies. For the aspirants to tyranny are either the principal men of the state, who in democracies are demagogues and in oligarchies members of ruling houses, or those who hold great offices, and have a long tenure of them '. States are preserved when their destroyers are at a distance. S jr and sometimes also because they are near, for the fear of them makes the government keep in band the state. Wherefore the ruler who has a care of the state should invent terrors, and bring distant dangers near, in order that the citizens may be on their guard, and, like sentinels in a night-watch, never relax their attention. He should endeavour too by help of the laws 9 1 vi. 7. § 4. ^ Supra c. 6. § 6. ' Cp. c. 5. § 6. DAVIS P 2 I o HoTv to avoid J^volution in V. 8 to control the contentions and quarrels of the notables, and to prevent those who have not hitherto taken part in them from being drawn in. No ordinary man can discern the beginning ''^of evil\ but only the true statesman. / lo As to the change produced in oligarchies and constitutional . ' governments'^ by the alteration of the qualification, when this y''^ &*. yya ^ arises, not out of any variation in the census but only out of the increase of money, it is well to compare the general .valuation of property with that of past years, annually in those |cities in which the census is taken annually, and in larger 1308b;clties every third or fifth year. If the whole is many times greater or many times less than when the rates were fixed at the previous census, there should be power given by law to raise or lower the qualification as the amount is greater or less. 11 Where in the absence of any such provision the standard is raised, a constitutional government passes into an oligarchy, and an oligarchy is narrowed to a rule of families ; where the standard is lowered, constitutional government becomes democracy, and oligarchy either constitutional government or democracy. 12 It is a principle common to democracy, oligarchy^, and "7. every other form of government not to allow the dispropor- jtionate increase of any citizen, but to give moderate honour for I a long time rather than great honour for a short time. For men are easily spoilt ; not every one can bear prosperity. But if this rule is not observed, at any rate the honours which are ' given all at once should be taken away by degrees and not all at once. Especially should the laws provide against any one 1 Cp. c. 4. §§ 1-3. =* Cp. c. 3. § 8 ; c, 6. §§ 16-18. ' Or, adding Kal fxovapxia, 'monarchy,' with many MSS. and Bekker's first edition. Oligarchy and Democracy 211 having too much power, whether derived from friends oi V. S money ; if he has, he and his followers should be sent out of the country^. And since innovations creep in through the 13 private life of individuals, there ought to be a magistracy which will have an eye to those whose life is not in harmony with the government, whether oligarchy or democracy or any other. And for a like reason an increase of prosperity in any part of ^ the state should be carefully watched. The proper remedy i^ for this evil is always to give the management of affairs and offices of state to opposite elements ; such opposites are the virtuous and the many, or the rich and the poor. Another way is to combine the poor and the rich in one body, or to increase the middle class : thus an end will be put to the revolutions which arise from inequality. But above all every state should be so administered and so 15 regulated by law that its magistrates cannot possibly make ; ' ' 1-/, money ^. In oligarchies special precautions should be used ' f.-f-r"/}, i^^. against this evil. For the people do not take any great 16 -.{Lii-r it*^ offence at being kept out of the government — indeed they are rather pleased than otherwise at having leisure for their private business — but what irritates them is to think that their rulers are stealing the public money ; then they are doubly annoyed ; for they lose both honour and profit. If office brought no 17 profit, then and then only could democracy and aristocracy be combined ; for both notables and people might have their 1309 a wishes gratified. All would be able to hold office, which is the aim of democracy, and the notables would be magistrates, which is the aim of aristocracy. And this result may be 18 accomplished when there is no possibility of making money X ' Cp^c. 3. § 3; iii. 13. § 15. » Cp. c. 13. § 14. P 2 212 Oligarchy and Democracy Preserved v. 8 out of the offices ; for the poor will not want to have them when there is nothing to be gained from them — they would [rather be attending to their own concerns; and the rich, who do not want money from the public treasury, will be able to take them ; and so the poor will keep to their work and giow X rich, and the notables will not be governed by the lower class, 19 In order to avoid peculation of the public money, the transfer of the revenue should be made at a general assembly of the citizens, and duplicates of the accounts deposited with the different brotherhoods, companies, and tribes. And honours should be given by law to magistrates who have the reputation 20 of being incorruptible. In democracies the rich should be spared ; not only should their property not be divided, but their incomes also, which in some states are taken from them imperceptibly, should be protected. It is a good thing to prevent the wealthy citizens, even if they are willing, from undertaking expensive and useless public services, such as the giving of choruses, torch-races, and the like. In an oligarchy, on the other hand, great care should be taken of the poor, and ^- lucrative offices should go to them ; if any of the wealthy ' classes insult them, the offender should be punished more severely ^ than one of their own class for a like offence ^ Provision should be made that estates pass by inheritance and not by gift, and no person should have more than one inheri- tance ; for in this way properties will be equalized, and more 21 of the poor rise to competency. It is also expedient both in a democracy and In an oligarchy to assign to those who have less share in the government (for example, to the rich in I a democracy and to the poor in an oligarchy) an equality or ' preference in all but the principal offices of state. The latter ^ Or, ' than if he had wronged one of his own class.' by Loyalty and Moderation 213 should be entrusted chiefly or only to members of the govern- V. 8 ing class. There arejjj^gg^ualifications required in those who have to fill the highest offices — (l) first of all, Joyalty to the 9 ' • established constitution ; ^ the greatest administrative ■^ • capacity; (3) virtue and justice of the kind proper to each ^, form of government ; for, if what is just is not the same in all governments, the quality of justice must also differ. There may be a doubt howevei, when all these qualities do not meet 2 in the same person, how the selection is to be made ; suppose, for example, a good general is a bad man and not a friend to 1309 b the constitution, and another man is loyal and just, which should we choose ? In making the election ought we not to consider two points ? what qualities are common, and what are rare. Thus in the choice of a general, we should regard his skill rather than his virtue ; for few have military skill, 5 but many have virtue. In keeping watch or in any office of stewardship, on the other hand, the opposite rule should be observed ; for more virtue than ordinary is required in the holder of such an office, but the necessary knowledge is of a sort which all men possess. It may, however, be asked what a man wants with virtue if 4 he have political ability and is loyal, since these two qualities alone will make him do what is for the public interest. But may not men have both of them and yet be deficient in self- control ? If, knowing and loving their own interests, they do not always attend to them, may they not be equally negligent of the interests of the public ? Speaking generally, we may say that whatever legal enact- 5 ments are held to be for the interest of states, all these preserve states. And the great preserving principle is the one which If 214 Preservatives of V. 9 has been repeatedly mentioned' — to have a care that the loyal 6| citizens should outnumber the disloyal. Neither should we forget the mean, which at the present day is lost sight of in perverted forms of government : for many practices which appear to be democratical are the ruin of democracies, and many which appear to be oligarchical ve the ruin of oligarchies. 7 Those who think that all virtue is to be found in their own party principles push matters to extremes ; they do not con- sider that disproportion destroys a state. A nose which varies from the ideal of straightness to a hook or snub may still be of good shape and agreeable to the eye;,,but if the excess be P. adaptation of education to the form of government^, and yet \ „.^hckcc in our own day this principle is universally neglected. The 12 best laws, though sanctioned by every citizen of the state, will be of no avail unless the young are trained by habit and education in the spirit of the constitution, if the laws are democratical, democratically, or oligarchically if the laws are oligarchical. For there may be a want of self-discipline in states as well as in individuals. Now, to have been educated 13 in the spirit of the constitution is not to perform the actions in which oligarchs or democrats delight, but those by which the existence of an oligarchy or of a democracy is made possible. Whereas among ourselves the sons of the ruling class in an oligarchy live in luxury -, but the sons of the poor are hardened by exercise and toil, and hence they are both more inclined and better able to make a revolution ^. And in democracies i,j of the more extreme type there has arisen a false idea of freedom which is contradictory to the true interests of the ^ Cp. i. 13. § 15. 2 Cp. iv. II. § 6. * Cp. Pi. Rep. viii. 556 d. zi6 Origin of Tyranny V. 9|State. For two princi^^les are characteristic of democracy, the 15 [government of the majority and freedom. Men think that what is just is equal ; and that equality is the supremacy ot the popular will ; and that freedom and equality mean the doing what a man likes. In such democracies every one lives ^as he pleases, or in the words of Euripides, 'according to his i P*^f^** If- '^'^'^ fancy.' But this is all wrong; men should not think it « ^ islavery to live according to the rule of the constitution ; for it ^ <^ jis theij salvation. tL -^ I have now discussed generally the causes of the revolution f V^^ and destruction of states, and the means of their preservation r^-^ and continuance. J? >^ 10 I '^'ive still to speak of monarchy, and the causes of its <^ "V destruction and preservation. What I have said already ^ 1310 b respecting other forms of government applies almost equally ":^ 2 '•o royal and to tyrannical rule. For royal rule is ot the I S nature of an aristocracy, and a tyranny is a compound of S i -v*! oligarchy and democracy in their most extreme forms ; it is L ^ therefore most injurious to its subjects, being made up of two evil forms of government, and having the perversions and ^ errors of both. These two forms of monarchy differ in their veiy origin. The appointment of a king is the resource of ~ the better classes against the people, and he is elected by them out of their own number, because either he liimself or " his family excel in virtue and virtuous actions ; whereas a tyrant is chosen from the people to be their protector against • the notables, and in order to prevent them from being injured. A History shows that almost all tyrants have been demagogues I who gained the favour of the people by their accusation of the r notables ^. At any rate this was the manner in which the * Cp. c. 5. § 6 ; Plato, Rep. 565 d. Origin of Tyranny 217 tyrannies arose in the days when cities had increased in power. V. 10 Others which were older originated jn_the ambition of kings wanting to overstep the limits of their hereditary power and become despots. Others again grew out of the class which were chosen to be chief magistrates ; for in ancient times the . people who elected them gave the magistrates, whether civil or >5 • religious, a long tenure. Others arose out of the custom which oligarchies had of making some individual supreme over the highest offices. In any of these ^ ways an ambitious man 6 had no difficulty, if he desired, in creating a tyranny, since he had the power in his hands already, either as king or as one of the officers of state ^. Thus Pheidon at Argos and several others were originally kings, and ended by becoming tyrants ; Phalaris, on the other hand, and the Ionian tyrants, acquired the tyianny by holding great offices. Whereas Panaetius at Leontini, Cypselus at Corinth, Peisistratus at Athens, Diony- sius at Syracuse, and several others who afterwards became tyrants, were at first demagogues. And so, as I was saying, royalty ranks with aristocracy, fori 7 it is based upon merit, whether of the individual or of his' family, or on benefits conferred ^, or on these claims with power added to them. For all who have obtained this honour 8 have benefited, or had in their power to benefit, states and nations ; some, like Codrus, have prevented the state from "^ being enslaved in war ; others, like Cyrus, have given their country freedom, or have settled or gained a territory, like the "^ Lacedaemonian, Macedonian, and Molossian kings*. The 9 idea of a king is to be a protector of the rich against unjust 1311 a ^ Retaining toi/'tois, which is omitted in Bekker's second edition, apparently by mistake. "^ Cp. c. 5. § S. = Cp. iii. 14. § 12. ♦ Cp. c. II, § 2. 21 8 Tyranny^ Oligarchy^ Democracy V. 10 treatment, of the people against insult and oppression. Whereas a tyrant, as has often been repeated, has no regard to any public interest, but only to his private ends ; his aim is plea- ^o sure, the aim of a king, honour. Wherefore also in their desires they differ ; the tyrant is desirous of riches, the king, "^ of what brings honour. And the guards of a king are citizens, kfe u"^ •■ jl but of a^tyrant rnercejiaries ^ 11 That tyranny has all the vices both of democracy and oligarchy is evident. As of oligarchy so of tyranny, the end is wealth ; (for by wealth only can the tyrant maintain either his guard or his luxury). Both mistrust the people, and therefore deprive them of their arms. Both agree too in injuring the people and diiving them out of the city and 12 dispersing them. From democracy tyrants have borrowed the art of making war upon the notables and destroying them secretly or openly, or of exiling them because they are rivals and stand in the way of their power ; and also because plots against them are contrived by men of this class, who either 13 want to rule or escape subjection. Hence Periander advised Thrasybulus " to cut off the tops of the tallest ears of corn, meaning that he must always put out of the way the citizens who overtop the rest. And so, as I have already intimated, the beginnings of change are the same in monarchies as in other forms of government ; subjects attack their sovereigns out of fear or contempt, or because they have been unjustly treated by them. And of injustice, the most common form ! I is insult, another is confiscation of property. 14 The ends sought by conspiracies against monarchies, whether tyrannies or royalties, are the same as the ends sought by conspiracies against other forms of government. ' Cp. iii. 14. § 7. * Cp. iii. 13, § 16. The Overthrow of l^lonarchies 219 Monarchs have great wealth and honour which are objects of V. 10 desire to all mankind. The attacks are made sometimes against their lives, sometimes against the office ; where the sense of insult is the motive, against their lives. Any sort of 15 ijnsult (and there are many) may stir up anger, and when men ■ are angry, they commonly act out of revenge, and not from \ ambition. For example, the attempt made upon the Peisis- tratidae arose out of the public dishonour offered to the sister of Harmodius and the insult to himself. He attacked the tyrant for his sister's sake, and Aristogeiton joined in the attack for the sake of Harmodius. A conspiracy was also 16 formed against Periander, the tyrant of Ambracia, because, when drinking with a favourite youth, he asked him whether 1311 b by this time he was not with child by him. Philip, too, was attacked by Pausanias because he permitted him to be insulted by Attalus and his friends, and Amyntas the little, by Derdas, because he boasted of having enjoyed his youth. Evagoras of Cyprus, again, was slain by the eunuch to revenge an insult ; for his wife had been carried off by Evagoras' son. Many 17 conspiracies have originated in shameful attempts made by sovereigns on the persons of their subjects. Such was the attack of Crataeus upon Archelaus ; he had always hated the connexion with him, and so, when Archelaus, having promised him one of his two daughters in marriage, did not give him either of them, but broke his word and married the elder to the king of Elymaea, when he was hard pressed in a war against Sirrhas and Arrhibaeus, and the younger to his own son Amyntas, under the idea that he would then be less likely to quarrel with the son of Cleopatra — Crataeus made this slight a pretext for attacking Archelaus, though even a less reason would have sufficed, for the real cause of the estrange- 2 20 The Overthrow of Monarchies V. 10 ment was the disgust which he felt at his connexion with the 1 8 king. And from a hke motive Hellanocrates of Larissa con- spired with him ; for when Archelaus, who was his lover, did not fulfil his promise of restoring him to his country, he thought that the connexion between them had originated, not in affection, but in the wantonness of power. Parrhon, too, and Heracleides of Aenos, slew Cotys in order to avenge their father, and Adamas revolted from Cotys in revenge foi the wanton outrage which he had committed in mutilating him when a child. 19 ^ Many, too, irritated at blows inflicted on the person which they deemed an insult, have either killed or attempted to kill officers of state and royal princes by whom they have been injured ^ Thus, at Mitylene, Megacles and his friends attacked and slew the Penthalidae, as they were going about and striking people with clubs. At a later date Smerdis, who had been beaten and torn away from his wife by Penthilus, 20 slew him. In the conspiracy against Archelaus, Decamnichus stimulated the fury of the assassins and led the attack ; he was enraged because Archelaus had delivered him to Euripides to be scourged ; for the poet had been irritated at some remark made by Decamnichus on the foulness of his breath. Many other examples might be cited of murders and conspiracies which have arisen from similar causes. ^ 21 Fear is another motive which has caused conspiracies as well in monarchies as in more popular forms of government. I Thus Artapanes conspired against Xerxes and slew him, fearing that he would be accused of hanging Darius against his orders — he being under the impression that Xerxes would ' Or ; ' Many persons too, even of those connected with the govern- ment or the royal family,' taking twv irepi, etc. with the subject. caused by Insult^ Fear^ Contempt 221 forget what he had said in the middle of a meal, and that the V. 10 offence would be foroiven. 1 O 1 .7 T Another motive is contempt, as in the case of Sardanapulus, ,3 "^ ' whom some one saw carding wool with his women, if the story-tellers say truly ; and the tale may be true, if not of him, of some one else \ Dion attacked the younger Dionysius 23 because he despised him, and saw that he was equally despised by his own subjects, and that he was always drunk. Even the friends of a tyrant will sometimes attack him out of con- tempt ; for the confidence which he reposes in them breeds contempt, and they think that they will not be found out. The expectation of success is likewise a sort of contempt ; 24 the assailants are ready to strike, and think nothing of the danger, because they seem to have the power in their hands. Thus generals of armies attack monarchs ; as, for example, Cyrus attacked Astyages, despising the effeminacy of his life, and believing that his power was w^orn out. Thus, again, Seuthes the Thracian conspired against Amadocus, whose general he was. And sometimes men are actuated by more than one motive, 25 like Mithridates, who conspired against Ariobarzanes, partly out of contempt and partly from the love of gain. Bold natures, placed by their sovereigns in a high military position, are most likely to make the attempt in the expecta- tion of success ; for courage is emboldened by power, and the union of the two inspires them with the hope of an easy victory. Attempts of which the motive is ambition arise from other causes. There are men who will not risk their lives in the 26 hope of gains and rewards however great, but who nevertheless ^ Cp. i. II. § 8. 222 Overthrow of ISdonarchies ^. V. 10 regard the killing of a tyrant simply as an extraordinary action vt which will make them famous and honourable in the world ; 27 they wish to acquire, not a kingdom, but a name. It is rare, however, to find such men ; he who would kill a tyrant must 28 be prepared to lose his life if he fail. He must have the resolution of Dion, who, when he made war upon Dionysius, took with him very few troops, saying, ' that whatever measure of success he might attain would be enough for him, even if he were to die the moment he landed ; such a death would be welcome to him.' But this is a temper to which few can attain. 29 Once more, tyrannies, like all other governments, are 1312 b destroyed from without by some opposite and more powerful form of government. That such a government will have the will to attack them is clear ; for the two are opposed in 30 principle ; and all men, if they can, do what they will. Democracy is also antagonistic to tyranny, on the principle of Hesiod, ' Potter hates Potter,' because they are nearly akin, for the extreme form of democracy is tyranny , and royalty and aristocracy are both alike opposed to tyranny, because they are constitutions of a different type. And therefore the Lacedaemonians put down most of the tyrannies, and so did the Syracusans during the time when they were well governed. 31 Again, tyrannies are destroyed from within, when the ^\ reigning family are divided among themselves, as that of i Gelo was, and more recently that of Dionysius ; in the case of Gelo because Thrasybulus, the brother of Hiero, flattered the son of Gelo and led him into excesses in order that he might rule in his name. Whereupon the family conspired to get rid of Thrasybulus and save the tyranny ; but the party who con- Especially of Tyrannies 223 spired ^ with them seized the opportunity and drove them all V. 10 out. In the case of Dionysius, Dion, his own relative, 32 attacked and expelled him with the assistance of the people ; he afterwards perished himself. There are two chief motives which induce men to attack » tyrannies — hatred and ^contempt. Hatred of tyrants is i inevitable, and contempt is also a frequent cause of their destruction. Thus we see that most of those who have 33 acquired, have retained their power, but those who have inherited ^, have lost it, almost at once ; for living in luxurious ease, they have become contemptible, and offer many oppor- tunities to their assailants. Anger, too, must be included under hatred, and produces the same effects. It is oftentimes 34 even more ready to strike — the angry are more impetuous in making an attack, for they do not listen to reason. And men ' are very apt to give way to their passions when they are insulted. To this cause is to be attributed the fall of the Peisistratidae and of many others. Hatred is more reasonable, 35 but anger is accompanied by pain, which is an impediment to i reason, whereas hatred is painless ^ In a word, all the causes which I have mentioned as destroying the last and most unmixed form of oligarchy, and the extreme form of democracy, may be assumed to affect tyranny ; indeed the extreme forms of botli are only tyrannies distributed among several persons. Kingly rule is little 36 affected by external causes, and is, therefore, lasting ; it is generally destroyed from within. And there are two ways 1 in which the destruction may come about; (i) when the 1313 a i * Omitting KaT inserted by Bekker in 2nd ed. ' Cp. Plato, Laws, iii. 695. ^ Cp. Rhetoric, ii. 4. § 31, 2 24 Overthrorv of Monarchies V. 10 members of the royal family quarrel among themselves, and •> /© when the kings attempt to administer the state too much 37 after the fashion of a tyranny, and to extend their authority contrary to the law. There are now no royalties ; monarchies, where they exist, are^^ tyrannies. For the rule of a king is over voluntary subjects, and he is supreme in all important matters ; but in our own day men are more upon an equality, and no one is so immeasurably superior to others as to repre- sent adequately the greatness and dignity of the office. Hence mankind will not, if they can help, endure it, and any one who obtains power by force or fiaud is at once thought to be 38 a tyrant. In hereditary monarchies a further cause of destruc- tion is the fact that kings often fall into contempt, and, although possessing not tyrannical but only royal power, are apt to outrage others. Their overthrow is then readily I effected ; for there is an end to the king when his subjects do not want to have him, but the tyrant lasts, whether they like him or not. The destmction of monarchies is to be attributed to these _ X i and the like causes. '^^'^pyJ ^^ ii And they are preserved, to speak generally, by the opposite hi *v causes; or, if we consider them separately, (l)joyalty is »?*»»0**ee> pi-eserved by the limitation of its powers. The more re- stricted the functions of kings, the longer their power will last unimpaired ; for then they are more moderate and not so despotic in their ways ; and they are less envied by their I 2 subjects. This is the reason why the kingly office has lasted so long among the Molossians. And for a similar reason it has continued among the Lacedaemonians, because there it was always divided between two, and afterwards further ' Omitting Kai with Bekker's and ed. Preservation of "Monarchies 225" limited by Theopompus in various respects, more particularly V. 11 by the establishment of the Ephoralty. He diminished the power of the kings, but established on a more lasting basis the kingly office, which was thus made in a certain sense not less, but greater. There is a story that when his wife once 3 asked him whether he was not ashamed to leave to his sons a royal power which was less than he had inherited from his father, he replied, ' No indeed, for the power which I leave to them will be more lasting.' As to (2) tyrannies, they are preserved in two most 4 opposite ways. One of them is the old traditional method in which most tyrants administer their government. Of such arts Periander of Corinth is said to have been the great master, and many similar devices may be gathered from the Persians in the administration of their government. There 5 are also the ancient prescriptions for the preservation of a tyranny, in so far as this is possible ; viz. that the tyrant should lop off those who are too high ; he must put to death men of spirit : he must not allow common meals, clubs, education, and the like ; he must be upon his guard against 1313 b anything which is likely to inspire either courage or confidence among his subjects ; he must prohibit literary assemblies or < other meetings for discussion, and he must take every means to prevent people from knowing one another (for acquaintance begets mutual confidence). Further, he must compel the 6 inhabitants to appear in public and live ^ at his gates •* ; then he will know what they are doing ; if they are always kept under, they will learn to be humble. In short, he should practise these and the like Persian and barbaric arts which all have the same object. A tyrant should also endeavour to 7 ' Or, 'at their doors.' DAVIS Q s> 2 25 The Devices of Tyra7iny 11 know what each of his subjects says or does, and should employ spies, like the ' female detectives ' at Syracuse, and the eavesdroppers whom Hiero was in the habit of sending to any place of resort or meeting ; for the fear of informers prevents people from speaking their minds, and if they do, 8 they are more easily found out. Another^ art of the tyrant is to sow quarrels among the citizens ; friends should be embroiled with friends, the people with the notables, and the rich with one another. Also he should impoverish his subjects ; he thus provides money for the support of his guards ■", and the people, having to keep hard at work, are 9 prevented from conspiring. The Pyramids of Egypt afford -* an example of this policy ; also the offerings of the family of Cypselus, and the building of the temple of Olympian Zeus by the Peisistratidae, and the great Polycratean monuments at Samos ; all these works were alike intended to occupy the lo people and keep them poor. Another practice of tyrants is to multiply taxes, after the manner of Dionysius at Syracuse, I who contrived that within five years his subjects should bring into the treasury their whole property. The tyrant is also fond of making war in order that his subjects may have some- thing to do and be always in want of a leader. And whereas the power of a king is preserved by his friends, the character- istic of a tyrant is to distrust his friends, because he knows that all men want to overthrow him, and they above all have the power '^. ^ Reading fj re with Bekker's 2nd ed. * This, which is probably the meaning of the passage, cannot be elicited from the text as it stands. The addition is reijuired of some such phrase as avrhv naOiXfiv, which is not wholly without mj^nuscript authoiity. The Ways of Tyranny and oflyr ants 227 Again, the evil practices of the last and worst forms of V. 11 l democracy are all found in tyrannies. Such are the power 1 1 < * given to women in their families in the hope that they will inform against their husbands, and the licence which is allowed to slaves in order that they may betray their masters ; fpr slaves and women dp not conspire against tyrants ; and they are of course friendly to tyrannies and also to democracies, since under them they have a good time. For the people too would fain be a monarch, and therefore by them, as well as by 1 2 the tyrant, the flatterer is held in honour ; in democracies he is the demagogue ; and the tyrant also has his humble com- panions who flatter him. 1314 a /^^/t* ^ Hence tyrants are always fond of bad men, because they (Li^tty^ .' love to be flattered, but no man who has the spirit of a free- / ^ man in him will demean himself by flattery ; good men love others, but they do not flatter anybody. Moreover the bad 13 are useful for bad purposes; 'nail knocks out nail,' as the proverb says. It is characteristic of a tyrant to dislike every JJ , one who has dignity or independence ; he wants to be alone in his glory, but any one who claims a like dignity or asserts his independence encroaches upon his prerogative, and is hated by him as an enemy to his power. Another mark of a tyrant is 14 >» that he likes foreigners better than citizens, and lives with them and invites them to his table ; for the one are enemies, but the others enter into no rivalry with him. Such are the notes of the tyrant and the arts by which he preserves his power ; there is no wickedness too great for him. All that we have said may be summed up under three heads, hxii^^lo which answer to the three aims of the tyrant. These are, 15 (l) the humiliation of his subjects; he knows that a mean- spirited man will not conspire against anybody: (2) the crea- Q 3 / r 2 2.8 Preservation of Tyranny V. 11 tion of mistrust among tliem ; for a tyrant is not overthrown until men begin to have confidence in one another ; and this is the reason why tyrants are at war with the good ; they are under the idea that their power is endangered by them, not only because they will not be ruled despotically, but also because they are loyal to one another, and to other men, and do not inform against one another or against other men : 1 6 (3) the tyrant desires that his subjects shall be incapable of action, for no one attempts what is impossible, and they will not attempt to overthrow a tyranny, if they are powerless. Under these three heads the whole policy of a tyrant may be summed up, and to one or other of them all his ideas may be referred: (l) he sows distrust among his subjects; (2) he t^kes away their power ; (3) he humbles them. "TT 17 This then is one of the two methods by which tyrannies are preserved ; and there is another which proceeds upon iS a different principle of action. The nature of this latter method may be gathered from a comparison of the causes which destroy kingdoms, for as one mode of destroying kingly power is to make the office of king more tyrannical, so j<- the salvation of a tyranny is to make it more like the rule of I a king. But of one thing the tyrant must be careful ; he .■^ must keep power enough to rule over his subjects, whether they like him or not, for if he once gives this up he gives up 19 his tyranny. But though power must be retained as the foundation, in all else the tyrant should act or appear to act in 1314 b the character of a king. In the first place he should pretend I . a care of tlie public revenues, and not waste money in making presents of a sort at which the common people get excited when they see their miserable earnings taken from them and lavished on courtesans and strangers and artists. He should The Beneficent Despot 229 give an account of what he receives and of what he spends V. 11 » • (a practice which has been adopted by some tyrants) ; for then he will seem to be the manager of a household rather than a tyrant ; nor need he fear that, while he is the lord of 20 the city, he will ever be in want of money. Such a policy is much more advantageous for the tyrant when he goes from home, than to leave behind him a hoard, for then the garrison who remain in the city will be less likely to attack his power ; and a tyrant, when he is absent from home, has more reason to fear the guardians of his treasure than the citizens, for the one accompany him, but the others remain behind. In the 21 second place, he should appear to collect taxes and to require "^ • public services only for state purposes ; and that he may form a fund in case of war, he ought to make himself the guardian and treasurer of them, as if they belonged, not to him, but to the public. He should appear, not harsh, but dignified, and f when men meet him they should look upon him with reverence, and not with fear. Yet it is hard for him to be respected it 22 he inspires no respect, and therefore whatever virtues he may neglect, at least he should maintain the character of a states- / man, and produce the impression that he is one. Neither he nor any of his associates should ever be guilty of the least offence against modesty towards the young of either sex who are his subjects, and the women of his family should observe 23 5! a like self-control towards other women ; the insolence of women has ruined many tyrannies. In the indulgence of pleasures he should be the opposite of our modern tyrants, y » who not only begin at dawn and pass whole days in sensuality, but want other men to see them, that they may admire their happy and blessed lot. In these things a tyrant should be 24 especially moderate, or at any rate should not parade his \ices 230 Preservation of Tyranny V. 11 to the world ; for a drunken and drowsy tyrant is soon despised and attacked ; not so he who is temperate and wide awake. His conduct should be the very reverse of nearly everything which has been said before about tyrants. He J7» ought to adorn and improve his city, as though he were not 25 a tyrant, but the guardian of the state. Also he should 1315 a appear to be particularly earnest in the service of the Gods ; for if men think that a ruler is religious and has a reverence for the Gods, they are less afraid of suffering injustice at his hands, and they are less disposed to conspire against him, because they believe him to have the veiy Gods fighting on 26 his side. At the same time his religion must not be thought foolish. And he should honour men of merit, and make them think that they would not be held in more honour by the citizens if they had a free government. The honour he should distribute himself, but the punishment should be in- 27 flicted by officers and courts of law. It is a precaution which is taken by all monarchs not to make one person great ; but if one, then two or more should be raised, that they may look sharply after one another. If after all some one has to be made great, he should not be a man of bold spirit ; for such dispositions are ever most inclined to strike. And if any one is to be deprived of liis power, let it be diminished gradually, to ■ 28 not taken from him all at once^. The tyrant should abstain from all outrage ; in particular from personal violence and from wanton conduct towards the young. He should be especially careful of his behaviour to men who are lovers of honour ; for as the lovers of money are offended when their property is touched, so are the lovers of honour and the 29 virtuous when their honour is affected. Therefore a tyrant ' Cp. c. 8. § 12. The Beneficent Despot 231 ought either not to use force at all, or he should be thought V. 11 only to employ fatherly correction, and not to trample upon others ; and his acquaintance with youth should be supposed to arise from affection, and not from the insolence of power, and in general he should compensate the appearance of dis- honour by the increase of honour. Of those who attempt assassination they are the most 30 dangerous, and require to be most carefully watched who doi not care to survive, if they effect their purpose. Therefore 31 special precaution should be taken about any who think that either they or their relatives have been insulted ; for when men are led away by pnssion to assault others they are regard- less of themselves. As Heracleitus says, ' It is difficult to fight against anger ; for a man will buy revenge with life ^.' And whereas states consist of two classes, of poor men 32 and of rich, the tyrant should lead both to imagine that they are preserved and prevented from harming one another by his rule, and whichever of the two is stronger he should attach to his government ; for, having this advantage, he has no need either to emancipate slaves or to disarm the citizens ; either party added to the force which he already has, will make him stronger than his assailants. But enough of these details ; — what should be the general 33 policy of the tyrant is obvious. He ought to show himself tcs* his subjects in the light, not of a tyrant, but of the master of I a household and of a king. He should not appropriate what 1:315 b is theirs, but should be their guardian ; he should be moderate, 1 not extravagant in his way of life ; he should be the com- ' panion of the notables, and the hero of the multitude. For '34 then his rule will of necessity be nobler and happier, because ' Fragm. 69 (ed. MuIIach). 232 Short Duration of Tyrannies V. lljhe will rule over better men' whose spirits are not crushed, \over men to whom he himself is not an object of hatred, and 'of whom he is not afraid. His power too will be more lasting. Let his disposition be virtuous, or at least half '■■ virtuous ; and if he must be wicked, let him be half wicked only. 12 Yet no forms of government are so short-lived as oligarchy *; and tyranny. The tyranny which lasted longest was that of Orthagoras and his sons at Sicyon ; this continued for a hun- dred years. The reason was that they treated their subjects with moderation, and to a great extent observed the laws ; and in various ways gained the favour of the people by the care which they took of them. Cleisthenes, in particular, 2 was respected for his military ability. If report may be believed, he crowned the judge who decided against him in the games ; and, as some say, the sitting statue in the Agora of Sicyon is the likeness of this person. A similar story is told of Peisistratus, who is said on one occasion to have allowed himself to be summoned and tried before the Areo- pagus. 3 Next in duration to the tyranny of Orthagoras was that of the Cypselidae at Corinth, which lasted seventy-three years and six months : Cypselus reigned thirty years, Periander forty-four, and Psammetichus the son of Gordius three. 4 Their continuance was due to similar causes : Cypselus was a popular man, who during the whole time of his rule never had a body-guard ; and Periander, although he was a tyrant, 5 was a great soldier. Third in duration was the rule of the Peisistratidae at Athens, but it was interrupted ; for Peisis- tratus was twice driven out, so that during three-and-thirty • Cp. i. 5. § 3. Criticism of Via to 253 years he reigned only seventeen ; and his sons reigned V. 12 eighteen — altogether thirty-five years. Of other tyrannies, that of Hiero and Gelo at Syracuse was the most lasting. Even this, however, was short, not more than eighteen years 6 in all ; for Gelo continued tyrant for seven years, and died in the eighth ; Hiero reigned for ten years, and Thrasybulus was driven out in the eleventh month. In fact, tyrannies generally have been of quite short duration. I have now gone through all the causes by which consti- 7 tutional governments and monarchies are either destroyed or 1316 a preserved. In the Republic of Plato ^, Socrates treats of revolutions, but not well, for he mentions no cause of change which peculiarly affects the first or perfect state. He only says 8 that nothing is abiding, but that all things change in a certain cycle ; and that the origin of the change is a base of numbers which are in the ratio of four to three, and this when com- bined with a figure of five gives two harmonies — (he means when the number of this figure becomes solid) ; he conceives that nature will then produce bad men who will not submit '^ to education ; in which latter particular he may very likely be not far wrong, for there may well be some men who \ cannot be educated and made virtuous. But why is such 9 a cause of change peculiar to his ideal state, and not rather common to all states, nay to everything which comes into being at all ? ''■ Or how is the state specially changed by the agency of time, which, as he declares, makes all things change ? And things which did not begin together, change together ^, for example, if something has come into being the ^ Rep. viii, 546. " Plating a note of interrogation after niraPdWeiv, Or : • And 234 Criticism of Plato V. 12 day before the completion of the cycle, it will change with it. ^ ^ Further, wliy should the perfect state change into the Spartan ? 10 for governments more often take an opposite form than one akin to them. The same remark is applicable to the other changes ; he says that the Spartan constitution changes jinto an oligarchy, and this into a democracy, and this again 1 1 into a tyranny. And yet the contrary happens quite as often ; for a democracy is even more likely to change into an oligarchy ^ than into a monarchy. Further, he never says whether tyranny is, or is not, liable to revolutions, and if it is, what is the cause of them, or into what form it changes. And the reason is, that he could not very well have told : for there is no rule ; according to him it should revert to the first and 12 best, and then there would be a complete cycle. But in point of fact a tyranny often changes into a tyranny, as that at Sicyon changed from the tyranny of Myron into that of Cleisthenes ; into oligarchy, as the tyranny of Antileon did at Chalcis ; into democracy, as that of Gelo did at Syracuse ; into aristocracy, as at Carthage, and the tyranny of Charilaus 13 at Lacedaemon. Often an oligarchy changes into a tyranny, like most of the ancient oligarchies in Sicily; for example, the oligarchy at Lcontini changed into the tyranny of Panae- tius ; that at Gela into the tyranny of Cleander ; that at Rhegium into the tyranny of Anaxilaus ; the same thing has 14 happened in many other states. And it is absurd to suppose that the state changes into oligarchy merely because [as Plato in the period of time which, as he saj's, makes all things change, things which did not begin together change together.' Bekker in his 2nd edition has altered the reading of the MSS. Sja -n rov xpovov to 5ia ye rdv xpovov. The rendering of the text agrees with either reading ; that of the note with the reading of the MSS. only. ^. Criticism of Plato 235- says '] the ruling class are lovers and makers of money, V. 12 and not because the very rich think it unfair that the very poor 1316 b should have an equal share in the government with themselves. Moreover, in many oligarchies there are laws against making money in trade. But at Carthage, which is a democracy, there is no such prohibition ; and yet to this day the Cartha- ginians have never had a revolution. _I^t is absurd too for him 15 ^ to say that an oligarchy is two cities, one of the rich, and the 0 » other of the poor". Is not this just as much the case in the Spartan constitution, or in any other in which either all do not possess equal property, or in which all are not equally good men ? Nobody need be any poorer than he was before, 16 and yet the oligarchy may change all the same into a demo- cracy, if the poor form the majority ; and a democracy may change into an oligarchy, if the wealthy class are stronger than the people, and the one are energetic, the other in- different. Once more, although the causes of revolutions are 17 ^ very numerous, he mentions only one^, which is, that the citizens become poor through dissipation and debt, as though he thought that all, or the majority of them, were originally rich. This is not true : though it is true that when any of the leaders lose their property they are ripe for revolution ; but, when anybody else, it is no great matter. And an iS oligarchy does not more often pass into a democracy than into any other form of goveinment. Again, if men are deprived of the honours of' state, and are wronged, and insulted, they make revolutions, and change forms of government, even although they have not wasted their substance because they ' Rep. viii. 550 E. * Rep. viii. 551 D. ' Rep. viii. 555 D. 2 3 <5 Criticism of Plato 12 might do what they liked — of which extravagance he declares excessive freedom to be the cause '. Finally, although there are many forms of oligarchies and democracies, Socrates speaks of their revolutions as though there were only one form of either of them. ' Rep. viii. 564. BOOK VI Q If- 1^ We have now considered the varieties of the deliberative VI. 1 or supreme power in states, and the various arrangements of law-courts and state offices, and which of them are adapted to different forms of government ^. We have also spoken of the destruction and pieservation of states, how and from what causes they arise ". Of democracy and all other forms of govei'nment there are 2 many kinds ; and it will be well to assign to them severally the modes of organization which are proper and advantageous to each, adding what remains to be said about them. More- 7, over, we ought to consider the various combinations of these modes themselves ^ ; for such combinations make constitutions overlap one another, so that aristocracies have an oligarchical character, and constitutional governments incline to demo- cracies *. When I speak of the combinations which remain to be 4 considered, and thus far have not been considered by us, I mean such as these: — when the deliberative part of the government and the election of officers is constituted oligar- chically, and the law-courts aristocratically, or when the courts and the deliberative part of the state are oligarchical, and the election to offices aristocratical, or when in any other way there is a want of harmony in the composition of a state. I have shown already what forms of democracy are suited 5 » Bk. iv. 14-16. 2 Bk. V. 3 Cp. Bk. iv. 7-9. < Cp. iv. S. § 3. 238 The Elpments of Democracy VI. 1 to particular cities, and what of oligarchy to particular peoples, and to whom each of the other forms of government is suited. 6 Further, we must not only show which of these governments is the best for each state, but also briefly proceed to con- sider^ how these and other forms of government are to be established. First of all let us speak of democracy, which will also bring to light the opposite form of government commonly 7 called oligarchy. For the purposes of this enquiry we need to ascertain all the elements and characteristics of democracy, since from the combinations of these the varieties of demo- 8 cratic government arise. There are several of these differing from each other, and the difference is due to two causes. One (l) has been already mentioned" — differences of popu- I lation ; for the popular element may consist of husbandmen, or of mechanics, or of labourers, and if the first of these be added to the second, or the third to the two others, not only does the democracy become better or worse, but its 9 very nature is changed. A second cause (2) remains to be mentioned : the various properties and characteristics of ! democracy, when variously combined, make a difference. For one democracy will have less and another will have more, and another will have all of these characteristics. There is an advantage in knowing them all, whether a man wishes to establish some new form of democracy, or only to remodel 10 an existing one '. Founders of states try to bring together all the elements which accord with the ideas of the several constitutions ; but this is a mistake of theirs, as I have already remarked ^ when speaking of the destruction and preservation * Cp. iv. 2. § 5. * Cp. iv. 4. § 21, s Cp. iv. I. § 7. ■♦ V. 9. § 7. The Nature of Democracy 239 of states. We will now set forth the requirements, ethical VI. 1 character, and aims of such states. The basis of a democratic state is liberty ; which, according 2 to the common opinion of men, can only be enjoyed in such 1317 b a state — this they affirm to be the great end of every demo- K^p^ u ii" cracy '. One principle of liberty is for all to rule and be 2 ruled in turn, and indeed democratic justice is the application • of numerical not proportionate equality; whence it follows that the majority must be supreme, and that whatever the majority approve must be the end and the just. Every citizen, it is said, must have equality, and therefore in a democracy the poor have more power than the rich, because there are more of them, and the will of the majority is supreme. This, 3 then, is one note of liberty which all democrats affirm to be the principle of their state. Another is that a man should X • live as he likes ^. This, they say, is the privilege of a freeman ; and, on the other hand, not to live as a man likes is the mark of a slave. This is the second characteristic of democracy, 4 whence has arisen the claim of men to be ruled by none, if possible, or, if this is impossible, to rule and be ruled in turns ; and so it coincides with the freedom based upon equality [which was the first characteristic]. of de- ^CkoAe^ei*^^/^^ (3 ^ Such being our foundation and such the nature mocracv, its characteristics are as follows ^ : — the election ^-/w C/*t«tA^ of officers by all out of all: ar^d^ that all should rule overt , Mii^MMMMiiJ— ' citizens not only of those who are legitimate, but even of the illegitimate, and of those who have only one parent a citizen, whether father or mother ^ ; for nothing of this sort comes amiss to such a democracy. This is the way in which dema- 1 7 gogues proceed ; whereas the right thing would be to make 1 Cp. V. 5. "" Cp. iii. 5. § 7. 24<^ The Construction and VI. 4 no more additions when the number of the commonalty exceeds that of the notables or of the middle class, — beyond this not to go. When in excess of this point the state becomes dis- orderly, and the notables grow excited and impatient of the democracy, as in the insurrection at Cyrene ; for no notice is taken of a little evil, but when it increases it strikes the eye. 18 Measures like those which Cleisthenes-* passed when he wanted to increase the power of the democracy at Athens, or such as were taken by the founders of popular government at Cyrene, 19 are useful in the extieme form of democracy. Fresh tribes and brotherhoods should be established ; the private rites of families should be restricted and converted into public ones ; in short, every contrivance should be adopted which will mingle the citizens with one another and get rid of old connexions. 20 Again, the measures which are taken by tyrants appear all of them to be democratic ; such, for instance, as the licence per- mitted to slaves (which may be to a certain extent advantageous) and also that of women and children, and the allowing every- body to live as he likes ^. Such a government will have many supporters, for most persons would rather live in a disorderly than in a sober manner. 5 The mere establishment of a democracy is not the only or principal business of the legislator, or of those who wish to create such a state, for any state, however badly constituted, may last one, two, or three days ; a {ax greater difficulty is the 2 preservation of it. The legislator should therefore endeavour to have a firm foundation according to the principles already laid down concerning the preservation and destruction of states^; he should guard against the destructive elements, and should ' Cp. iii. 2. § 3; V. 3. § 5. "^ Cp. V. II. § II. » Cp. Bk. V. Preservation of Democracy 247 make laws, whether written or unwritten, which will contain VI. 5 all the preservatives of states. He must not think the truly 13-20 a democratical or oligarchical measure to be -that which will give the greatest amount of democracy or oligarchy, but that which will make them last longest ^. The demagogues of our own 3 day often get property confiscated ^ in the law-courts in order to please the people. But those who have the welfare of the state at heart should counteract them, and make a law that the i. property of the condemned which goes into the treasury should not be public but sacred. Thus offenders will be as much afraid, for they will be punished all the same, and the people, having nothing to gain, will not be so ready to condemn the accused. Care should also be taken that state trials are as 4 few as possible, and heavy penalties should be Inflicted on those who bring groundless accusations ; for it is the practice to indict, not members of the popular party, but the notables, although the citizens ought to be all equally attached to the state, or at any rate should not regard their rulers as enemies. Now, since in the last and worst form of democracy the 5 citizens are very numerous, and can hardly be made to assemble unless they are paid, and to pay them when there are no revenues presses hardly upon the notables (for the money must be obtained by a property-tax and confiscations and cor- rupt practices of the courts, things which have before now overthrown many democracies) ; where, I say, there are no revenues, the government should hold few assemblies, and the law-courts should consist of many persons, but sit for a few days only. This system has two advantages : first, the rich 6 do not fear the expense, even although they are unpaid them- selves when the poor are paid ; and secondly, causes are better 1 Cp.v. II. §§2, 3. " Cj.. V. 5. § 5. 248 A Patriotic Nobility VI. 5 tried, for wealthy persons, although they do not like to be j long absent from their own affairs, do not mind going for a few 7! days to the law-courts. Where there are revenues the dema- gogues should not be allowed after their manner to distribute the surplus ; the poor are always receiving and always wanting more and more, for such help is like water poured into a leaky cask. Yet the true friend of the people should see that they be not too poor, for extreme poverty lowers the character of I the democracy ; measures also should be taken which will give them lasting prosperity ; and as this is equally the interest of all classes, the proceeds of the public revenues should be accumulated and disti^ibuted among them, if possible, in such quantities as may enable them to purchase a little farm, or, at any 1320 b rate, make a beginning in trade and husbandry. And if this 9 benevolence cannot be extended to all, money should be dis- tributed in turn according to tribes or other divisions, and in the meantime the rich should pay the fee for the attendance of the poor at the necessary assemblies ; and should in return be excused from useless public services. By administering the state in this spirit the Carthaginians retain the affections of the people ; their policy is from time to time to send some of 10 them into their dependent towns, where they grow rich ^. It is also worthy of a generous and sensible nobility to divide the poor amongst them, and give them the means of going to work. The example of the people of Tarentum is also well deserving of imitation, for, by sharing the use of their own property with 1 1 the poor, they gain their good will ^. Moreover, they divide all their offices into two classes, one-half of them being elected by vote, the other by lot ; the latter, that the people may participate in them, and the former, that the state may be better 1 Cp. ii. II. § 15. * Cp. ii. 5. § 8. The variojts IQnds of Oligarchies 249 administered. A like result may be gained by dividing the VI. 5 same offices ^, so as to have two classes of magistrates, one chosen by vote, the other by lot. Enough has been said of the manner in which democracies 6 ought to be constituted. From these considerations there v/ill be no difficulty in see- ing what should be the constitution of oligarchies. We must put together in our minds each form of oligarchy by reasoning from its opposite, calculating the structure of each in relation to that of the opposite democracy. The first and best attempered of oligarchies is akin to a con- 2 stitutional government. In this there ought to be two standards \ of qualification ; the one high^ the other Iqy.- — the lower qualifying for the humbler yet indispensable offices and the higher for the superior ones. He who acquires the prescribed qualification should have the rights of citizenship. The nature of those admitted should be such as will make the entire 3 governing body stronger than those who are excluded, and the new citizen should be always taken out of the better class of the people. The principle, narrowed a little, gives another form of oligarchy ; until at length we reach the most cliquish and tyrannical of them all, answering to the extreme democracy, which, being the worst, requires vigilance in proportion to its 4 badness. For as healthy bodies and ships well provided with sailors may undergo many mishaps and survive them, whereas sickly constitutions and rotten ill-manned ships are ruined by the very least mistake, so do the worst forms of government 1321a require the greatest care. The populousness of democracies 5 generally preserves them (for number is to democracy in the place of justice based on proportion) ; whereas the preservation ^ Reading ttjs aiiTfjs apxfjs with Bekker's and ed. tt 2fo Hoiv to Organize an Oligarchy VI. 6 of an oligarchy clearly depends on an opposite principle, viz. good order. 7 As there are four chief divisions of the common people — husbandmen, mechanics, retail traders, labourers ; so also there are four kinds of military forces — the cavalry, the heavy infantry, the light-armed troops, the navy \ When the country is adapted for cavalry, then a strong oligarchy is likely to be established. For the security of the inhabitants depends upon a force of this sort, and only rich men can afford to keep horses. The second form of oligarchy prevails when there are heavy infantry "^ ; for this service is better suited to the rich X ' 2 than to the poor. But the light-armed and the naval element are wholly democratic ; and nowadays, when they are so numerous, if the two parties quarrel, the oligarchy are often worsted by them in the struggle. A remedy for this state of things may be found in the practice of generals who combine a proper contingent of light-armed troops with cavalry and 3 heavy-armed. And this is the way in which the poor get the better of the rich in civil contests ; being lightly armed, they fight with advantage against cavalry and heavy infantry. An oligarchy which raises such a force out of the lower classes raises a power against itself. And therefore, since the ages of the citizens vary and some are older and some younger, the fathers should have their own sons, while they are still young, tauglit the agile movements of light-armed troops ; and some, when they grow up, should be selected out of the youth, and yj^ 4 become light-armed warriors in reality. The oligarchy should also yield a share in the government to the people, either, as I said before, to those who have a property qualification ', or, as * Cp. iv. 3. §§ 2, 3. ^ Rc:idiiiE; o-nX'iTriv with Bekker's 1st cd. ' Cp. c. 6. § 2. T^he Necessary Offices of State 25-1 in the case of Thebes ', to those who have abstained for a VI. 7 certain number of years from mean employments, or, as at Massaha, to men of merit who are selected for their worthi- ness, whether [previously] citizens or not. The magistracies 5 j* of the highest rank, which ought to be in the hands of the governing body, should have expensive duties attached to them, and then the people will not desire them and will take no offence at the privileges of their rulers when they see that they pay a heavy fine for their dignity. It is fitting also that 6 the magistrates on entering office should oifer magnificent sacrifices or erect some public ediiice, and then the people who participate in the entertainments, and like to see the city decorated with votive offerings and buildings, will not desire an alteration in tlie government, and the notables will have memorials of their munificence. This, however, is anything 7 but the fashion of our modern oligarchs, who are as covetous of gain as they are of honour ; oligarchies like theirs may be well described as petty democracies. Enough of the manner 1321b in which democracies and oligarchies should be organized. Next in order follows the right distribution of offices, their 8 number, their nature, their duties, of which indeed we have already spoken ^. No state can exist not having the necessary offices, and no state can be well administered not having the offices which tend to preserve harmony and good order. In 2 small states, as we have already remarked ^, there need not be many of them, but in larger there must be a larger number, and we should carefully consider which offices may properly "T^ be united and which separated. First among necessary offices is that which has the care of 3 j , 1 Cp. iii. 5. § 7. -Cp. iv. 15, QiCiJUt, ^ Cp. iv. 15. §§ 5-7. 2f2 Offices — the Criminal Executive VI. 8 the market; a magistrate should be appointed to inspect con- jtracts and to maintain order. For in every state there must inevitably be buyers and sellers who will supply one another's wants ; this is the readiest way to make a state self-sufficing and so fulfil the purpose for which men come together into one ^ ^ 4 state ^. A second office of a similar kind undertakes the super: vision and embellishment of public and private buildings, the 'maintaining and repairing of houses and roads, the prevention lof disputes about boundaries and other concerns of a like nature. 5 This is commonly called the office of City-warden, and has various departments, which, in more populous towns, are shared among different persons, one, for example, taking charge of the 6 walls, another of the fountains, a third of harbours. JThere -*' is another equally necessary office, and of a similar kind, having to do with the same matters without the walls and in the country : — the magistrates who hold this office are called Wardens of the country, or Inspectors of the woods. Besides ^ these three there is a fourth office of receivers of taxes, who have under their charge the revenue which they distribute among the various departments ; these are called Receivers or ^ 7 Treasurers. Another officer registers all private contracts, and •^ • decisions of the courts, all public indictments, and also all preliminary proceedings. This office again is sometimes sub- divided, in which case one officer is appointed over all the- rest. These officers are called Recorders or Sacred Recorders, Presidents, and the like. / 8 Next to these comes an office of which the duties are the most necessary and also the most difficult, viz. that to which is committed the execution of punishments, or the exaction of * .. - » Cp. i. 2. § 8 ; Nic. Eth. v. 6. § 4; PI. Rep. ii. 369. offices Militarv and Civil 25-3 fines from those who are posted up according to the registers ; VI. 8 and also the custody of prisoners. The difficulty of this office ^^^^ ^ arises out of the odium which is attached to it ; no one will undertake it unless great profits are to be made, and any one who does is loth to execute the law. Still the office is necessary ; for judicial decisions are useless if they take no effect ; and if society cannot exist without them, neither can it exist with- out the execution of them. It is an office which, being so lo unpopular, should not be entrusted to one person, but divided! among several taken from different courts. In like manner an effort should be made to distribute among different persons the writing up of those who are registered as public debtors. Some sentences should be executed by officers who have other functions ; penalties for new offences should be exacted by new offices ; and as regards those which are not new, when one court has given judgment, another should exact the penalty ; for example, the wardens of the city should exact the fines imposed by the wardens of the agora, and others again should exact the fines imposed by them. For penalties are more likely to be ii exacted when less odium attaches to the exaction of them ; but a double odium is incurred when the judges who have passed also execute the sentence, and if they are always the executioners, they will be the enemies of all. In many places one magistracy has the custody of the prisoners, while another executes the sentence, as, for example, ' the Eleven ' at Athens. It is well to separate off the jailor- 12 ship, and try by some device to render the office less unpopular. For it is quite as necessary as that of the executioner ; but good men do all they can to avoid it, and worthless persons cannot safely be trusted with it ; for they themselves require a guard, and are not fit to guard others. There ought not there- 13 hj 2 f 4 offices 'Military and Civil VI. 8 fore to be a single or permanent officer set apart for this duty ; but it should be entrusted to the young, wherever they are organized into a band or guard, and different magistrates acting T in turn should take charge of it. These are the indispensable officers, and should be ranked first : — next in order follow others, equally necessary, but of 14 higher rank, and requiring great experience and fidelity. Such are the offices to which are committed the guard of the city, I » and other military functions. Not only in time of war but of peace their duty will be to defend the walls and gates, and to muster and marshal the citizens. In some states there are many such offices ; in others there are a few only, while small 15 states are content with one ; these officers are called generals 1322 b or commanders. Again, if a state has cavalry or light-armed 1 troops or archers or a naval force, it will sometimes happen .'that each of these departments has separate officers, who are called admirals, or generals of cavalry or of infantry. And there are subordinate officers called naval and military captains, and captains of horse ; having others under them : — all these 16 are included in the department of war. Thus much of military command. But since many, not to say all, of these offices handle the ^ * public money, there must of necessity be another office which examines and audits them, and has no other functions. Such officers are called by various names — Scrutineers, Auditors, 17 Accountants, Controllers. Besides all these offices there is another which is supreme over them, and to this, which in a democracy presides over the assembly, is often entrusted both the introduction and the ratification of measures. For that power which convenes the people must of necessity be the head of the state. In some places they are called 'probuli,' offices of J{eli(no}i — Summary zjj because they hold previous deliberations, but in a democracy VI. 8 more commonly 'councillors^.' These are the chief political 18 offices. Another set of officers is concerned with the maintenance PcnF t/stilS of religion ; priests and guardians see to the preservation and repair of the temples of the gods and to other matters of religion. One office of this sort may be enough in small places, but in 119 larger ones there are a great many besides the priesthood ; for i example, superintendents of sacrifices, guardians of shrines, treasurers of the sacred revenues. Nearly connected with these 20 there are also the officers appointed for the performance of the public sacrifices, except any which the law assigns to the priests ; such officers derive their dignity from the public hearth of the city. They are sometimes called archons, sometimes kings ^, and sometimes prytanes. These, then, are the necessary offices, which may be summed a i up as follows : offices concerned with matters of religion, with war, with the revenue and expenditure, with the market, with the city, with _the harbours, with the country ; also with the courts of law, with the records of contracts, with execution of sentences, with custody of prisoners, with audits and scrutinies and accounts of magistrates ; lastly, there are those which pre- side over the public deliberations of the state. There are like- 22 wise magistracies characteristic of states which are peaceful and prosperous, and at the same time have a regard to good order : such as the offices of guardians of women, guardians of the laws, guardians of children, and directors of gymnastics ; also superintendents of gymnastic and Dionysiac contests, and 1323 ? of other similar spectacles. Some of these aie clearly not 23 democratic offices ; for example, the guardianships of women » Cp. iv. 15. § II. « Cp. iii. 14. § 14. 2y6 Summary VI. 8 and children ^ — the poor, not having any slaves, must employ both their women and children as servants. 24 Once more : there are three forms of the highest elective I offices in states — guardians of the law, probuli, councillors, — of these, the guardians of the law are an aristocratical, the probuli an oligarcliical, the council a democratical institution. Enough of the different kinds of offices. ' Cp. iv. 15. § 13. BOOK VII He who would duly enquire about the best form of a state VII. 1 ought first to determine which is the most eligible life ; while this remains uncertain the best form of the state must also be uncertain ; for, in the natural order of things, those may be expected to lead the best life who are governed in the best manner of which their circumstances admit. We ought there- 2 fore to ascertain, first of all, which is the most generally eligible life, and then whether the same life is or is not best for the state and for individuals. Assuming that enough has been already said in exoteric discourses concerning the best life, we will now only repeat the statements contained in them. Certainly no one will dispute 3 the propriety of that partition of goods which separates them into three classes \ viz. external goods, goods of the body, and goods of the soul, or deny that the happy man must have all three. For no one would maintain that he is happy who 4 has not in him a particle of courage or temperance or justice or prudence, who is afraid of every insect which flutters past him, and will commit any crime, however great, in order to gratify his lust of meat or drink, who will sacrifice his dearest friend for the sake of half a farthing, and is as feeble and false in mind as a child or a madman. These propositions are 5 universally acknowledged as soon as they are uttered '^, but men 1 Cp. N. Eth. i. 8. § 2. 2 Omitting wffnfp, which is bracketed by Bekker in his second edition. 2 5*8 Goods of Fortune, and Goods of the Soul VII. 1 differ about the quantity which is desirable or the relative superiority of this or that good. Some think that a very moderate amount of virtue is enough, but set no limit to their desires of wealth, property, power, reputation, and the like. 6 To whom we reply by an appeal to facts, which easily prove I that mankind do not acquire or preserve virtue by the help of 1323 bl external goods, but external goods by the help of virtue, and that happiness, whether consisting in pleasure or virtue, or both, is more often found with those who are most highly cultivated in their mind and in their character, and have only a moderate share of external goods, than among those who possess external goods to a useless extent hut are deficient in I higher qualities ; and this is not only matter of experience, but, if reflected upon, will easily appear to be in accordance with 7 reason. Foj-, whereas external goods have a limit, like any other instrument \ and all things useful are of such a nature that where there is too much of them they must either do harm, '-or at any rate be of no use, to their possessors, every good of the soul, the greater it is, is also of greater use, if the epithet 8 ' useful ' as well as ' noble ' is appropriate to such subjects. No proof is required to show that the best state of one thing in relation to another is proportioned to the degree of excel- lence by which the natures corresponding to those states are separated from each other : so that, if the soul is more noble than our possessions or our bodies, both absolutely and in relation to us, it must be admitted that the best state of either 9 has a similar ratio to the other. Again, it is for the sake of the soul that goods external and goods of the body are eligible at all, and all wise men ought to choose them for the sake of the soul, and not the soul for the sake of them. 1 Cp. i. 8. § 15. Virtue the Source of Happiness 2^9 Let us acknowledge then that each one has just so much of VII. 1 happiness as he has of virtue and wisdom, and of virtuous and ° wise action. God is a witness to us of this truth ^ ; for he is happy and blessed, not by reason of any external good, but in himself and by reason of his own nature. And herein of necessity lies the difference between good fortune and happiness; for external goods come of themselves, and chance is the author of them, but no one is just or temperate by or through chance -. In like manner, and by a similar train of argument, the happy ii state may be shown to be that which is [morally] best and which acts rightly ; and rightly it cannot act without doing " right actions, and neither individual nor state can do right actions without virtue and wisdom. Thus the courage, justice, and 12 wisdom of a state have the same form and nature as the qualities which give the individual who possesses them the name of just, wise, or temperate. Thus much may suffice by way of preface: for I could not 13 avoid touching upon these questions, neither could I go through all the arguments affecting them ; these must be reserved for another discussion. Let us assume then that the best life, both for individuals and I states, is the life of virtue, having external goods enough for ' the performance of good actions. If there are any who con- ^^-^ * trovert our assertion, we will in this treatise pass them over, and consider their objections hereafter. There remains to be discussed the question. Whether the 2 happiness of the individual is the same as that of the state, or different ? Here again there can be no doubt — no one denies that they are the same. For those who hold that the well-being 2 ^ Cp. c. 3. § 10; N. Eth. X. 8. § 7 ; Met. xii. 7. * Ethics i. 9. § 6. S 2 26 o Is Contemplation hest^ or Action^ VII. 2 of the individual consists in his wealth, also think that riches make the happiness of the whole state, and those who value most highly the life of a tyrant deem that city the happiest which rules over the greatest number ; while they who approve an individual for his virtue say that the more virtuous a city 3 is, the happier it is. Two points here present themselves for consideration : first (i), which is the more eligible life, \ that of a citizen who is a member of a state, or that of an ' alien who has no political ties ; and again (2), which is the best form of constitution or the best condition of a state, either on the supposition that political privileges are given to all, or 4 that they are given to a majority only ? Since the good of the state and not of the individual is the proper subject of political thought and speculation, and we are engaged in a political dis- cussion, while the first of these two points has a secondary inteiest for us, the latter will be the main subject of our enquiry. 5 Now it is evident that the form of government is best in which every man, whoever he is, can act for the best and live happily. But even those who agree in thinking that the life of virtue is the most eligible raise a question, whether the life of business and politics is or is not more eligible than one which is wholly independent of external goods, I mean than a contemplative life, which by some is maintained to be the 6 only one worthy of a pliilosopher. For these two lives — the life of the philosopher and the life of the statesman — appear to have been preferred by those who have been most keen in the pursuit of virtue, both in our own and in other ages. Which is the better is a question of no small moment ; for the wise man, like the wise state, will necessarily regulate his 7 life according to the best end. There are some who think The Policy of War and Oppression 2.6 \ that while a despotic rule over otheis is tlie greatest injustice, VII. 2 to exercise a constitutional rule over them, even though not unjust, is a great impediment to a man's individual well-being. Others take an opposite view ; they maintain that the true life of man is the practical and political, and that every virtue admits of being practised, quite as much by statesmen and rulers as by private individuals. Others, again, are of opinion that g arbitrary and tyrannical rule alone consists with happiness ; indeed, * in some states the entire aim of the laws ^ is to give men despotic power over their neighbours. And, therefore, 9 although in most cities the laws may be said generally to be in a chaotic state, still, if they aim at anything, they aim at the maintenance of power : thus in Lacedaemon and Crete the system of education and the greater part of the laws are framed with a view to war^. And in all nations which are able to 10 gratify their ambition military power is held in esteem, for ex- ample among the Scythians and Persians and Thracians and Celts. In some nations there are even laws tending to stimulate the warlike virtues, as at Carthage, where we are told that men obtain the honour of wearing as many armlets as they have served \campaigns. There was once a law in Macedonia that he who 1 1 had not killed an enemy should wear a halter, and among tiie Scythians no one who had not slain his man was allowed to drink out of the cup which was handed round at a certain feast. Among the Iberians, a warlike nation, the number of enemies whom a man has slain is indicated by the number of spits which are fixed in the earth round his tomb ; and there are numerous 1 2 ^ Or, inserting kox before vv^av (apparently the reading of the old translator), 'in some casts the entire aim both of the constitution and the laws.' 2 Cp. Plato, Laws, i. 633 ff 262 War not the Supreme End VII. 2 ])ractices among other nations of a like kind, some of them established by law and others by custom. Yet to a reflecting mind it must appear very strange that the statesman should be always considering how he can dominate and tyrannize over 13 others, whether they will or not. How can that which is not even lawful be the business of the statesman or the legislator ? Unlawful it certainly is to rule without regard to justice, for there may be might where there is no right. The other arts and sciences offer no parallel ; a physiciaii is not expected to persuade or coerce his patients, nor a pilot 14 the passengers in his ship. Yet many appear to think that a despotic government is a true political form, and what men affirm to be unjust and inexpedient in their own case they are not ashamed of practising towards others ; they demand justice for themselves, but where other men are concerned 15 they care nothing about it. Such behaviour is irrational; unless the one party is born to command, and the other born to serve, in which case men have a right to command, not indeed all their fellows, but only those who are intended to be subjects ; just as we ought not to hunt mankind, whether for food or sacrifice, but only the animals which are intended for food or sacrifice, that is to say, such wild i6 animals as are eatable. And surely there may be a city 1325 a happy in isolation, which we will assume to be well-governed (for it is quite possible that a city thus isolated might be well- administered and have good laws) ; but such a city would not be constituted with any view to war or the conquest of 17 enemies — all that sort of thing must be excluded. Hence '**'we see very plainly that warlike pursuits, although generally \to be deemed honourable, are not the supieme end of all •things, but only means. And the good lawgiver should The False and True Idea of a T{uler 263 enquire liov/ states and races of men and communities VII. 2 may participate In a good life, and in the happiness which is attainable by them. His enactments will not be always the i8 same ; and where there are neighbours ' he will have to deal with them according to their characters, and to see what duties are to be performed towards each. The end at which the best form of government should aim may be properly made a matter of future consideration ^. Let us now address those who, while they agree that the 3 life of virtue is the most eligible, differ about the manner of practising it. For some renounce political power, and think that the life of the freeman is different from the life of the statesman and the best of all ; but others think the life of the statesman best. The argument of the latter is that he who does nothing cannot do well, and that virtuous activity is identical with happiness. To both we say : ' you are partly right and partly wrong.' The first class are right in affirming that the life of the freeman is better than the life of the despot ; for there is nothing grand or noble 2 in having the use of a slave, in so far as he is a slave ; or in issuing commands about necessary things. But it is an error to suppose that every sort of rule is despotic like ^ that of a master over slaves, for there is as great a difference between the rule over freemen and the rule over slaves as there is between slavery by nature and freedom by nature, about which I have said enough at the commencement of this treatise ^. And it is equally a mistake to place inac- 3 tivity above action, for happiness is activity, and the actions of the just and wise are the realization of much that is noble. 1 Cp. ii. 6. § 7 ; 7. § 14. 2 Cp. c. 14. 3 Cp. i. c. 5, 6,7. 2^4 T^f^^ False and True Idea of a l\uler VII. 3 But perhaps some one, accepting these premisses, may still maintain that supreme power is the best of all things, because the possessors of it are able to perform the greatest number 4 of noble actions. If so, the man who is able to rule, instead of giving up anything to his neighbour, ought rather to take away his power ; and the father should make no account of his son, nor the son of his father, nor friend of friend ; they should not bestow a thought on one another in com- parison with this higher object, for the best is the most eligible and ' doing well ' is the best. There might be some 1325 b truth in such a view if we assume that robbers and plunderers 6 attain the chief good. But this can never be ; and hence we /infer the view to be false. For the actions of a ruler cannot really be honourable, unless he is as much supeiior to other men as a husband is to a wife, or a father to his children, or a master to his slaves. And therefore he who violates the law can never recover by any success, however great, what he has already lost in departing from virtue. For equals share alike in the honourable and the just, as is just 6 and equal. But that the unequal should be given to equals, and the unlike to those who are like, is contrary to nature, and nothing which is contrary to nature is good. If, there- fore, there is any one ■* superior in virtue and in the power of performing the best actions, him we ought to follow and 7 obejf^ but he must have the capacity for action as well as virtue. If we are riglit in our view, and happiness is assumed to be virtuous activity, the active life will be the best, both for S the city collectively, and for individuals. Not that a life of action must necessarily have relations to othci-s, as some ' Cp. iii. 13. § 25, and 17. §7. The Conditiotis of the Perfect State 2.6j persons think, nor are those ideas only to be regarded VII. 3 as practical which are pursued for the sake of practical results, but much more the thoughts and contemplations which are independent and complete in themselves ; since virtuous activity, and therefore action, is an end, and even in the case of external actions the directing mind is most truly said to act. Neither, again, is it necessary that states which are 9 cut off from others and choose to live alone should be inactive ; for there may be activity also in the parts ; there are many ways in which the members of a state act upon one another. The same thing is equally true of every individual. If this 10 were otherwise, God and the universe, who have no external actions over and above their own energies ', would be far enough from perfection. Hence it is evident that the same life is best for each individual, and for states, and for mankind collectively. Thus far by way of introduction. In what has preceded 4 I have discussed other forms of government ; in what remains, the first point to be considered is what should be the conditions of the ideal or perfect state ; for the perfect state 2 cannot exist without a due supply of the means of life. And therefore we must presuppose many purely imaginary condi- tions ^, but nothing impossible. There will be a certain number of citizens, a country in which to place them, and the like. As the weaver or shipbuilder or any other artisan 3 must have the material proper for his work (and in proportion 1326 a as this is better piepared, so will the result of his art be nobler), so the statesman or legislator must also have the materials suited to him. First among the materials required by the statesman is 4 ' Cp. c. 1. § 10. 2 cp_ ii 6. § 7. 266 The Number of the Citizens VII. 4 j opulation : he will consider what should be the number and character of the citizens, and then what should be the size and character of the country. Most persons think that a state in order to be happy ouglit to be large ; but even if they are right, they have no idea what is a large and what a small 5 state. For they judge of the size of the city by the number of the inhabitants ; whereas they ought to regard, not their number, but their power. A city too, like an individual, has a work to do ; and that city which is best adapted to the fulfilment of its work is to be deemed greatest, in the same sense of the word great in which Hii:pocrates might be called greater, not as a man, but as a physician, than some one 6 else who was taller. And even if we reckon greatness by numbers, we ought not to include everybody, for there must always be in cities a multitude of slaves and sojourners and foreigners ; but we should include those only who are members of the state, and who form an essential part of it. The number of the latter is a proof of the greatness of a city ; but a city which produces numerous artisans and comparatively few soldiers cannot be great, for a great city is not to be confounded 7 with a populous one. Moreover, experience shows that a very populous city can rarely, if ever, be well governed ; since all cities which have a reputation for good government have a limit of population. We may argue on grounds of reason, and 8 the same result will follow. For law is order, and good law is good order ; but a very great multitude cannot be orderly : to introduce order into the unlimited is the work of a divine ' power — of such a power as holds together the universe. Beauty ^ 9 is realized in number and magnitude S and the state which com- ^i-xX bines magnitude with good order must necessarily be the most 1 Cp. Poet. 7. § 4. The Number of the Citizens 2(^7 beautiful. To the size of states there is a limit, as there is to VII. 4 other things, plants, animals, implements ; for none of these jo retain their natural power when they are too large or too small, but they either wholly lose their nature, or are spoiled. For example \ a ship which is only a span long will not be a ship at all, nor a ship a quarter of a mile long ; yet there may be a ship of a certain size, either too large or too small, which will still be a ship, but bad for sailing. In like manner a state ^^-^ ^ when composed of too few is not as a state ought to be, self- sufficing ; when of too many, though self-sufficing in all mere necessaries, it is a nation and not a state, being almost incap- able of constitutional government. For who can be the general of such a vast multitude, or who the herald, unless he have the voice of a Stentor ? A state then only begins to exist when it has attained a population sufficient for a good life in the political com- munity: it may indeed somewhat exceed this number. But, 12 ^-^^^^.^^^^ u ■ as I was saying, there must be a limit. What should be //' the limit will be easily ascertained by experience. For both governors and governed have duties to perform ; the special functions of a governor are to command and to judge. But 13 if the citizens of a state are to judge and to distribute offices according to merit, tlien they must know each other's characters ; where they do not possess this knowledge, both the election to offices and the decision of lawsuits will go wiong. When tlie population is very large they 1 are manifestly settled at haphazard, which clearly ought ( not to be. Besides, in an overpopulous state foreigners and 14 metics will readily acquire the rights of citizens, for who will find them out ? Clearly, then, the best limit of the population j > Cp. V. 9. § 7. 2^8 The Situation of the City VII. 4 of a state Is the largest number which suffices for the pur- ' ])oses of Hfe, and can be taken in at a single view. Enough concerning the size of a city. •^ • 5 Much the same principle will apply to the territory of the K state ; every one would agree in praising the state which I ,4,.- is most entirely self-sufficing; and that must be the state which is all-producing, for to have all things and to want nothing is sufficiency. In size and extent it should be such as may enable the inhabitants to live temperately and liberally in the enjoyment of leisured Whether we are right or wrong in laying down this limit we will enquire more precisely hereafter ^, when we have occasion to consider what is the right use of property and wealth : a matter which is much disputed, because men are inclined to rush into one of two extremes, some into meanness, others into luxury. 3 It is net difficult to determine the general character of the territory which is required ; there are, however, some points on which military authorities should be heard ; they tell us that it should be difficult of access to the enemy, and 1327 a easy of egress to the inhabitants. Further, we require that the land as well as the inhabitants of whom we were just now speaking should be taken in at a single view, for a country which is easily seen can be easily protected. As to the position of the city, if we could have what we wish, it should "4 be well situated in regard both to sea or land. This then is one principle, that it should be a convenient centre for the protection of the whole country : the other is, that it should be suitable for receiving the fruits of the soil, and also for the bringing in of timber and any other products. 6 Whether a communication with the sea is beneficial to 1 Cp. ii. 6. § 9. » Cp. c. S-io infra 'J). Proximity of the Sea^ Good or Evilt' z6^ a well-ordered state or not is a question which has often been VII. 6 asked. It is argued that the introduction of strangers brought up under other laws, and the increase of population, will be 1 adverse to good order (for a maritime people will always have a crowd of merchants coming and going), and that intercourse by sea is inimical to good government^. Apart from these 2 considerations, it would be undoubtedly better, both with a view to safety and to the provision of necessaries, that the city and territory should be connected with the sea ; the 3 defenders of a country, if they are to maintain themselves against an enemy, should be easily relieved both by land and by sea; and even if they are not able to attack by sea and land at once, they will have less difficulty in doing mischief to their assailant^ on one element, if they themselves can use both. Moreover, it is necessary that they should import fromg4 abroad what is not found in their own country, and that theyl should export what they have in excess; for a city ought 10* be a market, not indeed for others, but for herself. Those who make themselves a market for the world only do so for the sake of revenue, and if a state ought not to desire profit of this kind it ought not to have such an emporium. Nowadays we often see in countries and cities 5 dockyards and harbours very conveniently placed outside the city, but not too far off; and they are kept in dependence by walls and similar fortifications. Cities thus situated mani- festly reap the benefit of intercourse with their ports ; and any harm which is likely to accme may be easily guarded against by the laws, which will pronounce and determine who may hold communication with one another, and who may not. There can be no doubt that the possession of a moderate 6 ^ Cp. Plato, Laws, iv. 704 ff. 2 70 The Character of the Citi^^ens VII, 6 naval force is advantageous to a city ; the citizens require ]327bsuch a force for their own needs, and they should also be formidable to their neighbours in certain cases ^, or, if necessary, able to assist them by sea as well as by land. 7 Tiie proper number or magnitude of this naval force is relative to the character of the state ; for if her function is to take a leading part in politics I her naval power should be commensurate with the scale of her enterprises. The population of the state need not be much increased, since 8 there is no necessity that the sailors should be citizens : the marines who have the control and command will be freemen, ^nd belong also to the infontry ; and wherever there is a dense population of Perioeci and husbandmen, there will always be sailors moie than enough. Of this we see instances at the present day. The city of Heraclea, for example, although small in comparison with many others, can 9 man a considerable fleet. Such are our conclusions respect- ing the territory of the state, its harbour, its towns, its relations to the sea, and its maritime power. 7 Having spoken of the number of the citizens, we will proceed to speak of what should be their character. This is a subject which can be easily understood by any one who casts his eye on the more celebrated states of Hellas, and generally on the distribution of races in the habitable 2 world. Those who live in a cold climate and in [northern] ' Europe are full of spirit, but wanting in intelligence and skill ; and therefore they keep their freedom, but have no political organization, and are incapable of ruling over others. Whereas the natives of Asia are intelligent and ' Cp. ii. 6. § 7. ^ Reading ttoKitikuv with the MSS. and Bekker's first edition. The Character of the Citi'^ns 271 inventive, but they are wanting in spiiit, and therefore they are VII. 7 always in a state of subjection and slavery. But the Hellenic 3 race, which is situated between them, is likewise intermediate in character, being high-spirited and also intelligent ^. Hence it continues free, and is the best governed of any nation, and, if it could be formed into one state, would be able to rule the world. There are also similar differences in the different tribes 4 of Hellas ; for some of them are of a one-sided nature, and are intelligent or courageous only, while in others there is a happy combination of both qualities. And clearly those whom the legislator will most easily lead to virtue may be expected to be both intelligent and courageous. Some [like Plato ^] 5 say that the guardians should be friendly towards those whom they know, fierce towards those whom they do not know. Now, passion is the quality of the soul which begets 1328 a friendship and inspires affection ; notably the spirit within us is more stirred against our friends and acquaintances than against those who are unknown to us, when we think that we are despised by them ; for which reason Archilochus, com- 6 plaining of his friends, very naturally addresses his soul in these words, • For wert thou not plagued on account of friends ^ ? ' The power of command and the love of freedom are in all men based upon this quality, for passion is commanding and invincible. Nor is it right to say that the guardians should be 7 fierce towards those whom they do not know, for we ought not to be out of temper with any one ; and a lofty spirit is not * Cp. Plato, Rep. iv. 435 e, 436 A. * Rep. ii. 375. * Qr : ' For surely thou art not plagued on account of thy friends?' The line is probably corrupt. Better to read with Bergk, av fap Sfj iraph. (piXwv dnayxfo, ' for thou indeed wert plagued by friends.' 2 72 The Passionate Nahire VII. 7 fierce by nature, but only when excited against evil-doers. And this, as I was saying before, is a feeling which men show most strongly towards their friends if they think they 8 have received a wrong at their hands : as indeed is reason- able ; for, besides the actual injury, they seem to be de- prived of a benefit by those who owe them one. Hence the saying, ' Cruel is the strife of brethren ^ ; ' and again, ' They who love in excess also hate in excess *.' 9 Thus we have nearly determined the number and character of the citizens of our state, and also the size and nature of their territory. I say ' nearly,' for we ought not to require the same minuteness in theory as in fact^. 8 As in other natural compounds the conditions of a compo- site whole are not necessarily organic parts of it, so in a state or in any other combination forming a unity not everything 2 is a part, which is a necessary condition '. The members of an association have necessarily some one thing the same and common to all, in which they share equally or unequally ; 3 for example, food or land or any other thing. But where there are two things of which one is a means and the other an end, they have nothing in common except that the one receives what the other produces. Such, for example, is the relation in which workmen and tools stand to their work ; the house and the builder have nothing in common, but 4 the ait of the builder is for the sake of the house. And so states require property, but property, even though living beings are included in it *, is no part of a state ; for a state is ^ Eurip. Frag. 51 Dindorf. '' Cp. 12. § 9, infra. 3 Cp. iii. 5. § 2. * Cp. i. 4. § 2. The Necessary Conditions of a State 273 not a community of living beings only, but a community VII. 8 of equals, aiming at the best life possible. Now, whereas 5 happiness is the highest good, being a realization and perfect practice of virtue, whicli some attain, while others have little or none of it, the various qualities of men are clearly the reason why there are various kinds of states and many forms of government ; for different men seek after happiness in different ways and by different means, and so make for 1328 b themselves different modes of life and forms of government. - I3t<>vl«cr , We must see also how many things are indispensable to 6 fr the existence of a state, for what we call the parts of a state will be found among them. Let us then enumerate the functions of a state, and we shall easily elicit what we want : First, there must be food ; secondly, arts, for life requires 7 many instruments ; thirdly, there must be arms, for the members of a community have need of them in order to maintain authority both against disobedient subjects and against external assailants ; fourthly, there must be a certain amount of revenue, both for internal needs and for the - 1 purposes of war ; fifthlyj or rather first, there must be a care .^-^ \ of religion, which is commonly called worship ; sixthly, and \ / most necessary of all, there must be a power of deciding what is for the public interest, and what is just in men's dealings with one another. These are the things which every state may be said to 8 need. For a state is not a mere aggregate of persons, but a union of them sufficing for the purposes of life ^ ; and if any of these things be wanting, it is simply impossible that the community can be self-sufKcing. A state then 9 * Cp. supra, c, 5. § I. DAVI5 X 2 74 "^he Necessary Conditions of a State VII. S should be framed with a view to the fulfilment of these functions. There must be husbandmen to procure food, and artisans, and a warlike and a wealthy class, and priests, and judges to decide what is just ^ and expedient. 0 Having determined these points, we have in the next place to consider whether all ought to share in every sort of occupa- tion. Shall every man be at once husbandman, artisan, coun- cillor, judge, or shall we sup])Ose the several occupations just mentioned assigned to different persons ? or, thirdly, shall some employments be assigned to individuals and others common to all ? The question, however, does not occur in every state ; 2 as we were saying, all may be shared by all, or not all by all, but only some by some - ; and hence arise the differences of states, for in democracies all share in all, in oligarchies the 3 opposite practice prevails. Now, since we are here speaking of the best form of government, and that under which the state will be most happy (and happiness, as has been already said, cannot exist without virtue '), it clearly follows that in the state which is best governed the citizens who are absolutely and not merely relatively just men must not lead the life of kmechanics or tradesmen, for such a life is ignoble and inimical 4lto virtue*. Neither must they be husbandmen, since leisure is 1329 ai necessary both for the development of viitue and the perform- [ance of political duties. Again, there is in a state a class of warriors, and another of councillors, who advise about the expedient and determine matters of law, and these seem in an especial manner parts of a state. Now, should these two classes be distinguished, or 5 are both functions to be assigned to the same persons ? Here ' Reading SiKaiciii' with Bekker in his second edition. ' Cp. iv. 4 and 14. ' Cp. c. 8. § 5. ■• Cp. Plaio, Laws, xi. 919. The Governing Classes 275" again there is no difficulty in seeing that both functions will in VII. 9 one way belong to the same, in another, to different persons. To different persons in so far as their employments are suited, to different ages of life, for the one requires wisdom, and the' . other strength. But on the other hand, since it is an im- possible thing that those who are able to use or to resist force should be willing to remain always in subjection, from this point of view the persons are the same ; for those who carry „ arms can always determine the fate of the constitution. It 6 remains therefore that both functions of government should be entrusted to the same persons, not, however, at the same time, but in the order prescribed by nature, who has given to young men strength and to older men wisdom. Such a distribution of duties will be expedient and also just, for it is in accordance with desert. Besides, the ruling class should be the owners of. 7 property, for they are citizens, and the citizens of a state should! be in good circumstances ; whereas mechanics or any other/ class whose art excludes the art of virtue have no share in the] state. This follows from our first principle, for happiness can- not exist without virtue, and a city is not to be termed happy in regard to a portion of the citizens, but in regard to them all ^. And clearly property should be in their hands, since the hus- s bandmen will of necessity be slaves or barbarians or Perioeci ^. Of the classes enumerated there remain only the priests, and the manner in which their office is to be regulated is obvious. I No husbandman or mechanic should be appointed to it ; for 9 I the Gods should receive honour from the citizens only. Now since the body of the citizens is divided into two classes, the warriors and the councillors ; and it is beseeming that the worship of the Gods should be duly performed, and also a • Cp. ii. 5. §§ 27, 28 2 cp_ j„fj^^ ^ jQ_ ij J2^ i^, T 2 2. J 6 Wairiors — Councillors — Priests VII. 9 lest provided in their service for those who from age have j given up active life — to the old men of these two classes should »i«/i .was established, as tradition says, by a law of Sesostris in Oj- 2 Egypt and of Minos in Crete. The institution of common tiu txi^iiM tables also appears to be of ancient date, being in Crete as 3 old as the reign of Minos, and in Italy far older. The Italian historians say that there was a certain Italus king of Oenotria, from whom the Oenotrians were called Italians, and who gave the name of Italy to the promontory of Europe lying between the Scylletic and Lametic Gulfs, which are distant from one 4 another only half a day's journey. They say that this Italus converted the Oenotrians from shepherds into husbandmen, and besides other laws which he gave them, was the founder of their common meals ; even in our day some who are derived from him retain this institution and certain other laws of his. 5 On the side of Italy towards Tyrrhenia dwelt the Opici, who are now, as of old, called Ausones ; and on the side towards lapygia and the Ionian Gulf, in the district called Syrtis \ the ' Retaining the reading of the MSS., which Rckker in his second edition has altered into Sfprns, a conjecture of Goettling's. Ancient E(rypt^ Crete ^ Italy ^77 Chones, who are likewise of Oenotiian race. From this part VII. 10 of the world originally came the institution of common tables ; the separation into castes [which was much older] from Egypt, for the reign of Sesostris is of far greater antiquity than that of Minos. It is true indeed that these and many other things 7 have been invented several times over ^ in the course of ages, or rather times without number ; for necessity may be supposed to have taught men the inventions which were absolutely re- quired, and when these were provided, it was natural that other things which would adorn and enrich life should grow up by degrees. And we may infer that in political institutions the same rule holds. Egypt ^ witnesses to the antiquity of all 8 things, for the Egyptians appear to be of all people the most ancient ; and they have laws and a regular constitution [existing from time immemorial]. We should therefore make the best use of what has been already discovered ^, and try to supply defects. 1 have already remarked that the land ought to belong to 9 those who possess arms and have a share in the government*," and that the husbandmen ought to be a class distinct from them ; and I have determined what should be the extent and nature of the territory. Let me proceed to discuss the distribution of the land, and the character of the agricultural class ; for I do not think that property ought to be common, as some ' Cp. Plato, Laws, iii. 676 ; Aristotle, Metaph. xi. 8. 10745.10; and Pol. ii. 5. § 16 (note). 2 Cp. Metaph. i. i. § 16; Meteor, i. 14. 352 b. 19; Plato, Timaeus, 22 B ; Laws, ii. 656, 657. ^ Reading, with Bekker in his second edition, eiipijtifvots : which may have been altered into dprjixfuots from a confusion of up-qrai Tcpurepov in § 9 infra. ' Cp. supra, c. 9. §§ 5-7. 278 Private Landholders — Common steals VII. 10 [maintain^, but only that by friendly consent there should be 1330 aja common use of it ; and that no citizen should be in want of subsistence. As to common meals, there is a genejal agreement that a well- (''i , tu <.zK\n}>A 'J 'o ordered city should have them ; and we will hereafter explain ft^', u., . >i. A.^. what are our own reasons for taking this view. They ought, however, to be open to all the citizens *. And yet it is not easy for the poor to contribute the requisite sum out of their private means, and to provide also for their household. The . expense of religious worship should likewise be a public charge, ^ ^ The land must therefore be divided into two parts, one public and the other private, and each part should be subdivided, half of the public land being appropriated to the service of the Gods, and the other half used to defray the cost of the common meals ; while of the private land, half should be near the border, and the other near the city, so that each citizen having two lots they may all of them have land in both places ; there is justice and fairness in such a division ', and it tends to inspire unanimity among the people in their bordei- 12 wars. Where there is not this arrangement, some of them are too ready to come to blows with their neighbours, while others are so cautious that they quite lose the sense of honour. Wherefore there is a law in some places which forbids those who dwell near the border to take part in public deliberations about wars with neighbours, on the ground that their Interests 13 will pervert their judgment. For the reasons already mentioned, then, the land should be divided in the manner described. » Cp. ii. 5. « Cp. ii. 9. § 31. 3 Cp. Plato, Laws, V. 745, where the ssnie proposal is found. Aristotle, ill Rook ii. 6. § 15, coiideimis the division of lots which he here adepts. He The Land and its Cultivators 279 > The very best thing of all would be that the husbandmen should VII. 10 be slaves, not all of the same race^ and not spirited, for if they have no spirit they will be better suited for their work, and there will be no danger of their making a revolution. The next best thing would be that they should be Perioeci of foreign race ^, and of a like inferior nature ; some of them should be 14 the slaves of individuals, and employed on the private estates of men of property, the remainder should be the property of the state and employed on the common land ^. I will hereafter . pa explain what is the proper treatment of slaves, and why it is 1^"-^^^^ ff expedient that liberty should be always held out to them as{ the reward of their services. We have already said that the city should be open to the 11 land and to the sea *, and to the whole country as far as possible. In respect of the place itself our wish would be to find a situation for it, fortunate in four things. The first, health — this is a necessity : cities which lie towards the 2 east, and are blown upon by winds coming from the east, are the healthiest ; next in healthfulness are those which are sheltered from the north wind, for they have a milder winter. The site of the city should likewise be convenient both 1330 b for political administration and for war. With a view to the 3 latter it should afford easy egress to the citizens, and at the same time be inaccessible and difficult of capture to enemies^. There should be a natural abundance of springs and fountains in the town or, if there is a deficiency of them, great reservoirs may be established for the collection of rain-water, such as will not fail when the inhabitants are cut 1 Cp. Plato, Laws, vi. 777. ' Cp. c. 9. § 8. « Cp. ii. 7. § 23. * Cp. c. 5. § 3. ° Repetition of c. 5. § 3. 28o The City: Sanitary Conditions VII. 11 off from the country by war. Special care should be taken ■* of the health of the inhabitants, which will depend chiefly on the healthiness of the locality and of the quarter to which they are exposed, and secondly, on the use of pure water; this latter point is by no means a secondary consideration. For the elements which we use most and oftenest for the support of the body contribute most to health, and among these 5 are water and air. Wherefore, in all wise states, if there is a want of pure water, and the supply is not all equally good, the drinking water ought to be separated from that which is used for other purposes. As to strongholds, what is suitable to different forms of government varies : thus an acropolis is suited to an oligarchy or a monarchy, but a plain to a democracy; neither to an 6 aristocracy, but rather a number of strong places. The arrangement of private houses is considered to be more agreeable and generally more convenient if the streets are regularly laid out after the modein fashion which Hippo- damus ^ introduced ; but for security in war the antiquated mode of building, which made it dil^cult for strangers to get out of a town and for assailants to fmd their way in, is y preferable. A city should therefore adopt both plans of building : it is possible to arrange the houses irregularly, as husbandmen plant their vines in what are called ' clumps.' The whole town should not be laid out in straight lines, but only certain quarters and regions ; thus security and beauty will be combined. 8 As to walls, those who say ^ that cities making any pretension to military virtue should not have them, are quite out of date in their notions ; and they may see the cities ' Cp. ii. 8. § I. Cp. I'laio, Laws, vi. 778, 779. Mil it a ry T\eq u irem en ts i%\ which prided themselves on this fancy confuted by facts. VII. 11 True, there is little courage shown in seeking for safety 9 behind a rampart when an enemy is similar in character and not much superior in number ; but the superiority of the besiegers may be and often is beyond the power of men to resist, and too much for the valour of a few ; and if they are to be saved and to escape defeat and outrage, the strongest 1331 a wall will be the best defence of the warrior, more especially now that catapults and siege engines have been brought to such perfection. To hiive no walls would be as foolish ^o as to choose a site for a town in an exposed country, and to level the heights ; or as if an individual were to leave his , house unwalled, lest the inmates should become cowards. 1 Nor must we forget that those who have their cities surrounded 11 by walls may either take advantage of them or not, but cities which are unwalled have no choice. If our conclusions are just, not only should cities have walls, but care should be taken to make them ornamental, as well as useful for warlike purposes, and adapted to resist modern inventions. For as the assailants of a city do 12 all they can to gain an advantage, so the defenders should make use of any means of defence which have been already discovered, and should devise and invent others, for wlien men are well prepared no enemy even thinks of attacking them. As the walls are to be divided by guardhouses and towers 12 built at suitable intervals, and the body of citizens must be distributed at common tables, the idea will naturally occur that we should establish some of the common tables in the guardhouses. The arrangement might be as follows : 2 the piincipal common tables of the magistrates will occupy 282 Public Buildings VII. 12 a suitable place, and there also will be the buildings appro- priated to religious worship except in the case of those rites which the law or the Pythian oracle has restricted to a 3 special locality ^. The site should be a spot seen far and wide, which gives due elevation to virtue and towers over the neighbourhood. Near tliis spot should be established an agora, such as that which the Thessalians call the ' freemen's 4 agora ' ; from this all trade should be excluded, and no mechanic, husbandman, oi" any such person allowed to enter, unless he be summoned by the magistrates. It would be a charming use of the place, if the gymnastic exercises of 5 the elder men were performed there. For ' in this noble practice different ages should be separated -, and some of the magistrates should stay with the boys, while the grown- up men remain with the magistrates [i. e. in the fieeman's agoi-a] ; for the presence of the magistrates is the best mode u Qf inspiring true modesty and ingenuous fear. There should also be a traders' agora, distinct and apart from the other, in a situation which is convenient for tlie reception of goods both by sea and land. But in speaking of the magistrates we must not forget another section of the citizens, viz. the priests, for whom public tables should likewise be provided in their proper 7 place near the temples. The magistrates who deal with contracts, indictments, summonses, and the like, and those who have the care of the agora and of the city respectively, ought to be established near the agora and in some public place of meeting ; the neighbourhood of the traders' agora will be a suitable spot ; the upper agora we devote to * Cp. Plato, Laws, v. 738 ; vi. 759, 778 ; vlii. 848. * Or 'this institution should be diviiled according to ages.' The End of the State and the I^ leans 283 the life of leisure, the other is intended for the necessities of VII. 12 trade. The same order should prevail ^ in the country, for there 8 too the magistrates, called by some ' Inspectors of Forests,' and by others 'Wardens of the Country,' must have guard- houses and common tables while they are on duty ; temples I should also be scattered throughout the country, dedicated, I some to Gods, and some to heroes. But it would be a waste of time for us to linger over 9 details like these. The difficulty is not in imagining but in carrying them out. We may talk about them as much as we like, but the execution of them will depend upon fortune. Wherefore let us say no more about these matters for the present. Returning to the constitution itself, let us seek to 13 determine out of what, and what sort of, elements the state which is to be happy and well-governed should be composed. There are two things in which all well-being consists ; one of 2 them is the choice of a right end and aim of action, and the other the discovery of the actions which are means towards it ; for the means and the end may agree or disagree. Sometimes the right end is set before men, but in practice they fail to attain it ; in other cases they are successful in all the means, but tliey propose to themselves a bad end, and some- times they fail in both. Take, for example, the art of medicine ; physicians do not always understand the nature of health, and also the means which they use may not effect the desired end. In all arts and sciences both the end and the means should be equally within our control. The happiness and well-being which all men manifestly 3 desire, some have the power of attaining, but to others, from ^ Reading vtViixfiaQai with liekker's first edition. 284 The Good Life T{cquires External Goods VII. 13 some accident or defect of nature, the attainment of them is 1332 a not granted ; for a good life requires a supply of external goods, in a less degree when men are in a good state, in 4 a greater degree when they are in a lower state. Others again, who possess the condition of happiness, go utterly wrong from the first in the pursuit of it. But since our object is to discover the best form of government, that, namely, under which a city will be best governed, and since the city is best governed which has the greatest opportunity of obtaining happiness, it is evident that we must clearly ascertain the nature of happiness. 5 We have said in the Ethics \ if the arguments there adduced are of any value, that happiness is the realization and perfect exercise of virtue, and this not conditional, but absolute. And I used the term ' conditional ' to express that which is indispensable, and ' absolute ' to express that which is good in itself. Take the case of just actions ; just punishments and chastisements do indeed spring from a good principle, but they are good only because we cannot do without them — it would be better that neither individuals nor states should need anything of the sort — but actions which aim at honour 7 and advantage are absolutely the best. Tlie conditional action is only the choice - of a lesser evil ; whereas these are the foundation and creation of good. A good man may make the best even of poverty and disease, and the other ills of life ; but he can only attain happiness under the opposite conditions ^ As we have already said in the Ethics*, ' Cp. N. Eth. i. 7. § 15 ; X. 6. § 2 ; aiui cp. c. 8. § 5, supra. ^ Retaining the MSS. reading atptais with Bc-kker's first edition. ' N. Eth. i. 10. § 12-14. * N. Eih. iii. 4. §§ 4, 5 ; E. E. v.i. 15. § 4 ; M. M. Ii. y. § 3. The Good Life Requires External Goods 28 y the good man is he to whom, because he is virtuous, the VII. 13 absolute good is his good. It is also plain that his use 8 of other goods must be virtuous and in the absolute sense good. This makes men fancy that external goods are the cause of happiness, yet vv'e might as well say that a brilliant performance on the lyre was to be attributed to the instru- ment and not to the skill of the performer. It follows then from what has been said that some things the legislator must find ready to his hand in a state, others he must provide. And therefore we can only say : May 9 our state be constituted in such a manner as to be blessed with the goods of which fortune disposes (for we acknow- ledge her power) : whereas virtue and goodness in the state are not a matter of chance but the result of knowledge and purpose. A city can be virtuous only when the citizens who have a share in the government are virtuous, and in our state all the citizens share in the government ; let us then enquire how a man becomes virtuous. For even if we could 10 suppose all the citizens to be virtuous, and not each of them, yet the latter would be better, for in the virtue of each the virtue of all is involved. There are three things which make men good and virtuous: these are nature, habit, reason^. In the first place, every one 11 must be born a man and not some other animal ; in the second place, he must have a certain character, both of body and soul. But some qualities there is no use in having at birth, for they are altered by habit, and there are some 1332 b gifts of nature which may be turned by habit to good or bad. Most animals lead a life of nature, although in lesser 12 uarticulars some are influenced by habit as well. Man 1 Cp. N. Eth. X. 9. § 6. 285 Hovo IMen hccome Good VII. 13 has reason, in addition, and man only '. Wherefore nature, habit, reason must be in harmony with one another [for they I do not always agree] ; men do many things against habit and [J nature, if reason persuades them that they ought. We have already determined what natures are likely to be most easily moulded by the hands of the legislator ^. All else is the work of education ; we learn some things by habit and some by instruction. 14 Since every political society is comi)Osed of rulers and subjects, let us consider whether the relations of one to the other should interchange or be permanent '. For the education of the citizens will necessarily vary with the answer 3 given to this question. Now, if some men excelled others in the same degree in which gods and heroes are supposed to excel mankind in general, having in the first place a great advantage even in their bodies, and secondly in their minds, so that the superiority of the governors * over their subjects was patent and undis])utcd *, it would clearly be better that once for all the one class should rule and the others serve". 3 But since this is unattainable, and kings have no marked superiority over their subjects, such as Scylax affirms to be found among the Indians, it is obviously necessary on many grounds that all the citizens alike should take their turn of governing and being governed. Equality consists in the same treatment of similar persons, and no government can stand 4 which is not founded upon justice. For [if the government be unjust] every one in the country unites with the governed • Cp. i. 2. § lo. '^ Cp. supra, c. 7. § 4. ' Cp. iii. 6. § y. * Or, taking rofs a.p\o^ivoi^ with (fiavfpav, ' was tindisputed and patent to their subiects.' » Cp. i. 5. § 8; iii. 13. § 13. Same Persons Jailers aiid Subjects 287 in the desire to have a revolution, and it is an impossibility that VII. 14 the members of the government can be so numerous as to be stronger than all their enemies put together. Yet that governors should excel their subjects is undeniable. How all this is to be effected, and in what way they will respectively share in the government, the legislator has to consider. The subject has been already mentioned '. Nature herself has given the 5 principle of choice when she made a difference between old and young (though they are really the same in kind), of whom she fitted the one to govern and the others to be governed. No one takes offence at being governed when he is young, nor does he think himself better than his governors, espe- ' cially if he will enjoy the same privilege when he reaches the required age. . We conclude that from one point of view governors 6 land governed are identical, and from another different. And therefore their education must be the same and also different. 1333 a For he who would learn to command well must, as men say, first of all learn to obey ^. As I observed in the first part of this treatise, there is one rule which is for the sake of the rulers and another rule which is for the sake of the ruled ^ ; the former is a despotic, the latter a free government. 7 Some commands differ not in the thing commanded, but in the intention with which they are imposed. Wherefore, many apparently menial offices are an honour to the free youth by whom they are performed ; for actions do not differ as honourable or dishonourable in themselves so much as in the end and intention of them. But since we say * that the virtue 8 C\-'W i09' of the citizen and ruler is the same as that of the good man, I 1 Cp. c. 9. § 5. - Cp. iii. 4. § 14, ' Cp. iii. 6. § 6. * Cp. iii. 4 and 5. § 10. 28 8 Who TUN St Learn T^dc by Obedience VII. 14 and that the same person must first be a subject and then a ruler, the legislator has to see that they become good men, and by what means this may be accomplished, and what is the end of the perfect life. 9 Now the soul of man is divided into two parts, one of ! which has reason in itself, and the other, not having reason in itself, is able to obey reason \ And we call a man >igood because he has the virtues of these two parts. In which of them the end is more likely to be found is no lo matter of doubt to those who adopt our division ; for in the world both of nature and of art the inferior always exists for the sake of the better or superior, and the better or superior is that which has reason. The reason too, in I !)9r? ^\ I ^^^^ ordinary way of speaking, is divided into two parts, for ,1' |ii there is a practical and a speculative reason'^, and there must ' be a corresponding division of actions ; the actions of the naturally better principle are to be preferred by those who have it in their j)0wer to attain to both or to all, for that is always to every one the most eligible which is the highest 12 attainable by him. The whole of life is further divided I into two parts, business and leisui-e ^, war and peace, and all ■ actions into those which are necessary and useful, and those 13 which are honourable. And the preference given to one or the other class of actions must necessarily be like the preference given to one or other part of the soul and its I actions over the other ; there must be war for the sake of j)eace, business for the sake of leisure, things useful ' and necessary for the sake of things honourable. All these 1 C|.. N. Kth. i. 13. §§ IS, ly. " Cp. N. Eth. vi. I. § 5; 1 1. § 4. » N. Eth. X. 7, § 6. The Spartan Ideal Critic'iT^d 289 points the statesman should keep in view when he frames his VII. 14 laws ; he should consider the parts of the soul and their functions, and above all the better and the end ; he should 14 also remember the diversities of human lives and actions. For men must engage in business and go to war, but leisure 1333 b and peace are better; they must do what is necessary and I ^o-v^tjU fe- '"'^ useful, but what is honourable is better. In such principles children and persons of every age which requires education * should be trained. Whereas even the Hellenes of the 15 present day, who are reputed to be best governed, and the legislators who gave them their constitutions, do not appear to have framed their governments with a regard to the best end, or to have given them laws and education with a view to all the virtues, but in a vulgar spirit have fallen back on those which promised to be more useful and profitable. Many i5 modern writeis have taken a similar view : they commend the Lacedaemonian constitution, and praise the legislator for making conquest and war his sole aim ^, a doctrine which may be refuted by argument and has long ago been refuted by facts. For most men desire empire in the hope of accumu- 17 lating the goods of fortune ; and on this ground Thibron and all those who have written about the Lacedaemonian consti- tution have praised their legislator, because the Lacedae- monians, by a training in hardships, gained great power. But surely they are not a happy people now that their empire 18 has passed away, nor was their legislator right. How ridiculous is the result, if, while they are continuing in the observances of his laws and no one inteiferes with them they have lost the better part of life. These writers further 19 ' Plato, Laws, i. 628, 638. DAVIS U 290 spartan or 'Military Ideal ^„i.figf iixsf VII. 14 err about the sort of government which the legislator should approve, for the government of freemen is noble, and implies more virtue than despotic government \ Neither is a city to be deemed happy or a legislator to be praised because he trains his citizens to conquer and obtain dominion over their 20 neighbours, for there is great evil in this. On a similar principle any citizen who could, would obviously try to obtain the power in his own state — the crime which the Lacedae- monians accused king Pausanias of attempting ^, although he had so great honour already. No such principle and no law having this object is either statesmanlike or useful or 21 right. For the same things are best both for individuals and for states, and these are the things which the legislator ought to implant in the minds of his citizens. Neither should men \ study war with a view to the enslavement of those who \ ^ -do not deserve to be enslaved ; but first of all they should \<. /provide against their own enslavement, and in the second 1331 a place obtain empire for the good of the governed, and not for I the sake of exercising a general despotism, and in the third place they should seek to be masters only over those 22 who deserve to be slaves. Facts, as well as arguments, prove that the legislator should direct all his military and other measures to the provision of leisure and the establishment of peace. For most of these military states are safe only while they are at war ', but fall when they have acquired their empire ; like unused iron they lose their edge in time of peace. And for this the legislator is to blame, he never having ' taught them how to lead the life of peace. 15 Since the end of individuals and of states is the same, the I Cp. i. 5. § 2. * Cp. V. I. § 10 ; 7. § 4. ' Cp. ii. 9. § 34. spartan or Military Ideal 291 end of the best man and of the best state must also be VII. 15 the same ; it is therefore evident that there ought to exist in both of them the virtues of leisure ; for peace, as has been , often repeated, is the end of war, and leisure of toil. But 3 leisure and cultivation may be promoted, not only by those virtues which are practised in leisure, but also by some of those which are useful to business-^. For many neces- saries of life have to be supplied before we can have leisure. Therefore a city must be temperate and brave, and able to endure : for truly, as the proverb says, ' There is no leisure for slaves,' and those who cannot face danger like men are the slaves of any invader. Courage and endurance 3 are required for business and intellectual virtue for leisure, temperance and justice for both, more especially in times of peace and leisure, for war compels men to be just and temperate, whereas the enjoyment of good fortune and the leisure which comes with peace tends to make them insolent. Those, then, who seem to be the best off and to be 4 in the possession of every good, have special need of justice and temperance — for example, those (if such there be, as the poets say) who dwell in the Islands of the Blest ; they above all will need philosophy and temperance and justice, and all the more the more leisure they have, living in the midst of abundance. There is no difficulty in seeing why the state 5 that would be happy and good ought to have these virtues. If it be disgraceful in men not to be able to use the goods of life, it is peculiarly disgraceful not to be able to use them in time of peace — to show excellent qualities in action and war, and when they have peace and leisure to be no better than slaves. ' i. e. ' not only by some of the speculative but also by some of the practical virtues,' V 3 292 Need of a Higher Ideal of Life VII. 15 Wherefore we should not practise virtue after the manner of ^ the Lacedaemonians ^. For they, while agreeing with other 1334 b men in their conception of the highest goods, differ from the rest of mankind in thinking that they are to be obtained by the practice of a single virtue. And since these goods and the enjoyment of them are clearly greater than the enjoyment derived from the virtues of which they are the end, we must now consider how and by what means they are to be attained. 7 We have already determined that nature and habit and reason are required ^, and what should be the character of the citizens has also been defined by us. But we have still to consider whether the training of early life is to be that of reason or habit, for these two must accord, and when in accord they will then form the best of harmonies. Reason may make mistakes and fail in attaining the highest ideal of life, ' and 8 there may be a like evil influence of habit '. Thus much is clear in the first place, that, as in all other things, generation starts from a beginning, and that the ends of some beginnings are related to another end. Now, in men reason and mind are the end towards which nature strives, so that the generation and moral discipline of the citizens ought to be ordered with g a view to them. In the second place, as the soul and body are two, we see also that there aie two parts of the soul, the rational and the irrational*, and two corresponding states — ireason and a])petite. And as the body is prior in order of Jgeneration to the soul, so the irrational is prior to the rational. » Cp. ii. 9. § 34. » Cp. 13. § 12. • Or, 'and yet a man may be trained by habit as if the reason had not so erred.' * Cp. N. i:th. i. 13. § 9 ff. Nature and Habit Prior to J{eason 293 The proof is that anger and will and desire are implanted in VII. 15 children from their very birth, but reason and understandinal are developed as they grow older. Wherefore, the care of thq body ought to precede that of the soul, and the training of the appetitive part should follow : none the less our care of it must be for the sake of the reason, and our care of the body for the sake of the soul \ Since the legislator should begin by considering how the 16 frames of the childien whom he is rearing may be as good as possible, his first care will be about mariiage — at what age should his citizens marry, and who are fit to marry ? In 2 legislating on this subject he ought to consider the persons and their relative ages, that there may be no disproportion in them, and that they may not differ in their bodily powers, as will be the case if the man is still able to beget children while the woman is unable to bear them, or the woman able to bear while tlie man is unable to beget, for from these causes arise quarrels and differences between married persons. Secondly, he must consider the time at which the children will succeed to their /C > parents ; there ought not to be too great an interval of age, for 3 then the parents will be too old to deiive any pleasure from their affection, or to be of any use to them. Nor ought they 1335 a to be too nearly of an age ; to youthful marriages there are many objections — the children will be wanting in respect to their parents, who will seem to be their contemporaries, and disputes will arise in the management of the household. Thirdly, and 4 O ■ this is the point from which we digressed, the legislator must mould to his will the frames of newly-born children. Almost all these objects may be secured by attention to one point. Since the time of generation is commonly limited within the 5 ^ Cp. Plato, Rep. iii. 410. 2 94 T^h^ Physical Foundation VII. 16 age of seventy years in the case of a man, and of fifty in the case of a woman, the commencement of the union should con- 6 form to these periods. The union of male and female when too young is bad for the procreation of children ; in all other animals the offspring of the young are small and ill-developed, SI. and generally of the female sex, and therefore also in man, as is proved by the fact that in those cities in which men and women are accustomed to marry young, the people are small T and weak ; in childbirth also younger women suffer more, and more of them die ; some persons say that this was the meaning of the response once given to the Troezenians — [' Shear not the young field '] — the oracle really meant that many died because they married too young ; it had nothing to 8 do with the ingathering of the harvest. It also conduces to temperance not to marry too soon ; for women who marry early are apt to be wanton ; and in men too the bodily frame is stunted if they marry while they are growing (for there is 9 a time when the growth of the body ceases). Women should (marry when they are about eighteen years of age, and men at ;seven-and-thirty ^ ; then they are in the prime of life, and the 10 decline in the powers of both will coincide. Further, the cliildren, if their birth takes place at the time that may reasonably be expected, will succeed in their prime, when the fathers are already in the decline of life, and have nearly reached their term of three-score vears and ten. A Thus much of the age proper for marriage : the season of the year should also be considered ; according to our present custom, people generally limit marriage to the season of winter, 11 and they are right. The precepts of physicians and natural philosophers about generation should also be studied by the ' Oniiuiiig fj jjiiitpuv. J{egulations Concerning 'Marriage 297 parents themselves ; the physicians give good advice about VII. 16 the right age of the body, and the natural philosophers about the winds ; of which they prefer the north to the south. 1335 b What constitution in the parent is most advantageous to 12 the offspring is a subject which we will hereafter consider when we speak of the education of children, and we will only make a few general remarks at present. The temperament of an athlete is not suited to the life of a citizen, or to health, or to the procreation of children, anymore than the valetudinarian or exhausted constitution, but one which is in a mean between them. A man's constitution should be inured to labour, but 13 not to labour which is excessive or of one sort only, such as is practised by athletes ; he should be capable of all the actions of a freeman. These remarks apply equally to both parents. Women who are with child should be careful of themselves ; 14 they should take exercise and have a nourishing diet. The first of these prescriptions the legislator will easily carry into effect by requiring that they shall take a walk daily to some temple, where they can worship the gods who preside over birth ^. Their minds, however, unlike their bodies, they ought to keep unexercised, for the offspring derive their natures from their mothers as plants do from the earth. As to the exposure and rearing of children, let there be a 15 \) law that no deformed child shall live, but where there are too many (for in our state population has a limit), when couples have children in excess, and the state of feeling is averse to the exposure of offspring, let abortion be procured before sense - character of oligarchy creates oligarchy; and always the better the character, the better the government. Now for the exercise of any faculty or art a previous training and habituation are required ; clearly therefore for the practice of virtue. And since the whole city has one end,^ it is manifest that education should be one and the same for all, and that it should be public, and not private — not as at present, when every one looks after his own children separately, and gives them separate instruction of tlie sort which he thinks best ; the training in things which are of 4 common interest should be the same for all. Neither must b ^ *fTf4 \^^ suppose that any one of the citizens belongs to himself, for >J l^b r'''cy 'ill belong to the state, and are each of them a part I i of the state, and the care of each part is inseparable from the care of the whole. In this particular the Lacedaemonians arc to be pi-aised, for they take the greatest pains about their children, and make education the business of the state *. 2 That education should be regulated by law and should be an affair of state is not to be denied, but what should I Cp. V. 9. §§ 11-16. * Cp. N. Eili. X. 9. § 13. i' What is a Liberal Education^ 301 be the character of this public education, and how young VIII. 2 persons should be educated, are questions which remain to be considei-cd. For mankind are by no means agreed about the things to be taught, whether we look to virtue or the best life. Neither is it clear whether education is more concerned with intellectual or with moral virtue. The existing prac- 2 tice is perplexing ; no one knows on what principle we should proceed — should the useful in life, or should viitue, or should the higher knowledge, be the aim of our training ; all three opinions have been entertained. Again, about the 1337 b means there is no agreement ; for different persons, start- ing with different ideas about the nature of virtue, naturally disagree about the practice of it. There can be no doubt 3 that children should be taught those useful things which are really necessary, but not all things ; for occupations are divided into liberal and illiberal ; and to young children , should be imparted only such kinds of knowledge as will be useful to them without vulgarizing them. And any ^ occupation, art, or science, which makes the body or soul or mind of the freeman less fit for the practice or exercise of virtue, is vulgar ; wherefore we call those arts vulgar 5 (\ • jl .■ ItZ ■ which tend to deform the body, and likewise all paid employ- ' ments, for they absorb and degrade the mind. There are also some liberal arts quite proper for a freeman to acquire, but only in a certain degree, and if he attend to them too closely, in order to attain perfection in them, the same evil effects will follow. The object also which a man 6 sets before him makes a great difference ; if he does or learns anything for his own sake ^ or for the sake of his friends, or with a view to excellence, the action will not 1 Cp. iii, 4. § 13. 3 02 IVhat is a Liberal Education^ VIII. 2 appear illiberal ; but if done for the sake of others, the very same action will be thought menial and servile. The received subjects of instruction, as I have already remarked ^, are partly of a liberal and partly of an illiberal character. 3 The customary branches of education are in number four ; they are — (i) reading and writing, (2) gymnastic exercises, (3) musicj to which is sometimes added (4) drawing. Of these, reading and writing and drawing are regarded as useful for the purposes of life in a variety of ways, and gymnastic exercises are thought to infuse courage. Concerning music 2 a doubt may be raised — in our own day most men cultivate it for the sake of pleasure, but originally it was included in education, because nature herself, as has been often said, requires that we should be able not only to work well, but to use leisure well ; for, as I must repeat once and again "^, the -.3 first principle of all action is leisure. Both are required, but leisure is better than occupation ; and therefore the question must be asked in good earnest, what ought we to do when at leisure ? Clearly we ought not to be amusing ourselves, for then amusement would be the end of life. But if this is 4 inconceivable, and yet amid serious occupations amusement is needed more than at other times (for he who is hard at work has need of relaxation, and amusement gives relaxation, whereas occupation is always accompanied with exertion and effort), at suitable times we should introduce amusements, and they should be our medicines, for the emotion which they create in the soul is a relaxation, and 1338 a from the pleasure we obtain rest. Leisure of itself gives pleasure and happiness and enjoyment of life, which are 5 experienced, not by the busy man, but by those who have * § 3 supra. ^ As in vii. 15. §§ i, 2, and N, Kth. x. 6. The TJse of Music 303 leisure. For he who is occupied has in view some end which VIII. 3 he has not attained ; but happiness is an end which all men deem to be accompanied with pleasure and not with pain. This pleasure, however, is regarded differently by different persons, and varies according to the habit of individuals ; the ^ pleasure of the best man is the best, and springs from the noblest sources. It is clear, then, that there are branches 6 of learning and education which we must study with a view to the enjoyment of leisure, and these are to be valued for their own sake ; whereas those kinds of knowledge which are useful in business are to be deemed necessary, and exist for the sake of other things. And therefore our fathers 7 admitted music into education, not on the ground either of its necessity or utility, for it is not necessary, nor indeed useful "^ in the same manner as reading and writing, which are useful in money-making, in the management of a household, in the acquisition of knowledge and in political life, nor like drawing, useful for a more correct judgment of the works of artists, nor again like gymnastic, which gives health and strength ; for neither of these is to be gained from music. There remains, then, the use of music for intellectual enjoyment in leisure ; which appears to have been the reason of its introduc- tion, this being one of the ways in which it is thought that a freeman should pass his leisure ; as Homer says — 'How good is it to invite men to the pleasant feast V and afterwards he speaks of others whom he describes as inviting ' The bard who would delight them all ".' ^ Or, ' to invite Thalia to the feast,' an interpretation of the passage possibly intended by Aristotle, though of course not the original rneaning. ' Od. xvii. 385. 304 Educational Studies VIII. 3 And in another place Odysseus says there is no better way of passing life than v hen ' Men's hearts are merry and the banqueters in the hall, sitting in order, hear the voice of the minstrel ^.' 10 It is evident, then, that there is a sort of education in which parents should train their sons, not as being useful or necessary, but because it is liberal or noble. Whether this is of one kind only, or of more than one, and if so, what they are, and how they are to be imparted, must hereafter be 11 determined. Thus much we are now in a position to say that the ancients witness to us; for their opinion may be gathered from the fact that music is one of the received and traditional branches of education. Further, it is clear that children should be instructed in some useful things — for example, in reading and writing — not only for their usefulness, but also because many other sorts of knowledge are acquired through 12 them. With a like view they may be taught drawing, not to prevent their making mistakes in their own purchases, or in order that they may not be imposed upon in the buying 1338 b or selling of articles, but rather because it makes them judges of the beauty of the human form. To be always seeking after the useful does not become free and exalted 13 souls ^. Now it is clear that in education habit must go ; before reason, and the body before the mind ; and therefore boys should be handed over to the trainer, who creates in them the proper habit of body, and to the wrestling-master, who teaches them their exercises. 4 Of those stateswhich in ourowndayseem to take the greatest care of children, some aim at producing in them an athletic habit, but they only injure their forms and stunt their growth. 1 Od. ix. 7. ' Cp. Plato, Rep. vii. 525 ff. Physical Education 305* Although the Lacedaemonians have not fallen into this VIII. 4 mistake, yet they brutalize their children by laborious exercises ^ which they think will make them courageous. But in truth, 3 as we have often repeated, education should not be exclusively directed to this or to any other sirgle end. And even if we suppose the Lacedaemonians to be right in their end, they do not attain it. For among barbarians and among animals courage is found associated, not with the greatest ferocity, but with a gentle and lion-like temper. There are many races 3 who are ready enough to kill and eat men, such as the Achaeans and Heniochi, who both live about the Black Sea ^ ; and there are other inland tribes, as bad or worse, who all live by plunder, but have no courage. It is notorious that the 4 Lacedaemonians, while they were themselves assiduous in their laborious drill, were superior to others, but now they are beaten both in war and gymnastic exercises. For their ancient superiority did not depend on their mode of training their youth, but only on the circumstance that they trained i them at a time when others did not. Hence we may 5 infer that what is noble, not what is brutal, should have the first place ; no wolf or other wild animal will face a really noble danger ; such dangers are for the brave man '^. And 6 parents who devote their children to gymnastics while they neglect their necessary education, in reality vulgarize them ; for they make them useful to the state in one quality only, and even in this the argument proves them to be inferior to others. We should judge the Lacedaemonians not from 7 what they have been, but from what they are ; for now they have rivals who compete with their education ; formerly they had none. 1 Cp. N. Eth. vii. 5. § 2. " Cp. N. Etb. iii, 6. § 8. DAVIS 3J 30'5' Gymnastic 9"III. 4 It is an admitted principle that gymnastic exercises should be em])loyed in education, and that for children they should be of a lighter kind, avoiding severe regimen or painful toll, 8 lest the growth of the body be impaired. The evil of excessive training in early years is strikingly proved by 1339 a the example of the Olympic victoi'S ; for not more than two or three of tliem have gained a prize both as boys and as men ; their early training and severe gymnastic exercises exhausted 9 their constitutions. When boyhood is over, three years should be spent in other studies ; tlie period of life which follows may then be devoted to hard exercise and strict regimen. Men ouglit not to labour at the same time with their minds and with their bodies ^ ; for the two kinds of labour are opposed to one another — tlie labour of the body impedes the mind, and tiie labour of the mind the body. 5 Concerning music there are some questions which we have already raised ; these we may now resume and cairy further ; and our remarks will serve as a prelude to this or any other 3 discussion of the subject. It is not easy to determine the nature of music, or why any one should have a knowledge of it. Shall we say, for the sake of amusement and relaxation, like sleep or drinking, which are not good in themselves, but are pleasant, and at the same time 'make care to cease,' 3 as Euripides ' says ? And therefore men rank them with music, and make use of all three — sleep ^, drinking, music — to which some add dancing. Or shall we argue that music conduces to virtue, on the ground tliat it can form our minds and habituate us to true pleasures as our bodies are made by * Cp. Plato, Rep. vii. 5,^7 b. ^ Bacchae, 380. ' Reading (with Bekker's 2nd ed.) virv(f), a correction which seems necessary, and is suggested by vtrvov xai fjitOrji above. Music 307 gymnastic to be of a certain character ? Or shall we say that VIII. 5 it contributes to the enjoyment of leisure and mental cultiva- '^ tion, which is a third alternative? Now obviously youth are not to be instructed with a view to their amusement, for learn- ing is no pleasure, but is accompanied with pain. Neither is intellectual enjoyment suitable to boys of that age, for it is the end, and that which is imperfect cannot attain the perfect or end. But perhaps it may be said that boys learn music for 5 the sake of the amusement which they will have when they are grown up. If so, why should they learn themselves, and not, like the Persian and Median kings, enjoy the pleasure and instruction which is derived from hearing others ? (for 6 surely skilled persons who have made music the business and profession of their lives will be better performers than those who practise only to learn). If they must learn music, on the same principle they should learn cookery, which is absurd. And even granting that music may form the 7 character, the objection still holds : why should we learn ourselves ? Why cannot we attain true pleasure and form 1,339 b a correct judgment from hearing others, like the Lacedae- monians ? — for they, without learning vtiusic, nevertheless can correctly judge, as they say, of good and bad melodies. Or 8 again, if music should be used to promote cheerfulness and refined intellectual enjoyment, the objection still remains — why should we learn ourselves instead of enjoying the performances of others ? We may illustrate what we are saying by our conception of the Gods ; for in the poets Zeus does not himself sing or play on the lyre. Nay, we call professional performers vulgar ; no freeman would play or sing unless he were intoxicated or in jest. But these matters 9 may be left for the present. X 2 3o8 The Pleasure of Music VIII. 5 The first question is whether music is or is not to be a part of education. Of the three things mentioned in our discus- sion, which is it ? — Education or amusement or intellectual enjoyment, for it may be reckoned under all three, and seems 10 to share in the nature of all of them. Amusement is for the sake of relaxation, and relaxation is of necessity sweet, for it is the remedy of pain caused by toil, and intellectual enjoyment is universally acknowledged to contain an element not only of the noble but of the pleasant, for happiness 11 is made up of both. All men agree that music is one of the pleasantest things, whether with or without song ; as Musaeus says, ' Song is to mortals of all things the sweetest.' Hence and with good reason it is introduced into social gatherings and entertainments, because it makes the hearts of men glad : so that on this ground alone we may assume that 12 the young ought to be trained in it. For innocent pleasures are not only in harmony with the perfect end of life, but they also provide relaxation. And whereas men rarely attain the end, but often rest by the way and amuse themselves, not only with a view to some good, but also for the pleasure's sake, it may be well for them at times to find a refreshment in music. 13 It sometimes happens that men make amusement the end, for the end probably contains some element of pleasure, though not any ordinary or lower pleasure ; but they mistake the lower for the higher, and in seeking for the one find the other, since every pleasure has a likeness to the end of action ^ For the end is not eligible, nor do the pleasures which we have described exist, for the sake of any future good but of the past, that is to say, they are the alleviation of ' Cp. N. Eih. viLi3. §6. Music and Morals 309 past toils and pains. And we may infer this to be the VIII. 5 reason why men seek happiness from common pleasures. 14 But music is pursued, not only as an alleviation of past toi[j but also as providing recreation. And who can say 15 whether, having this use, it may not also have a nobler one ? In addition to this common pleasure, felt and shared in by all 13i0 a (for the pleasure given by music is natural, and therefore adapted to all ages and characters), may it not have also some influence over the character and the soul ? It must 16 have such an influence if characters are afl^ected by it. And that they are so affected is proved by the power which the songs of Olympus and of many others exercise ; for beyond question they inspire enthusiasm, and enthusiasm is an emotion of the ethical part of the soul. Besides, when 17 men hear imitations, even unaccompanied, by melody or rhythm, their feelings move in sympathy. Since, then, music is a pleasure, and. virtue consists in rejoicing and. loving and hating aright, there is clearly nothing which we are so much concerned to acquire and. to cultivate as the power of forming right judgments, and of taking delight in good dispositions and noble actions ^. Rhythm and melody supply imitations 1 S of anger and gentleness, and also of courage and temperance and of virtues and vices in general, which hardly fall short of the actual affections, as we know from our own experience, for in listening to such strains our souls undergo a change. The habit of feeling pleasure or pain at mere representations 19 is not far removed from the same feeling about realities ^ ; for example, if any one delights in the sight of a statue for its beauty only, it necessarily follows that the sight of '^ Cp. Plato, Rep. iii. 401, 402 ; Laws, ii. 658, 659. ' Cp. Plato, Rep. iii. 395. 310 The Harmojiies VIII. 5 the oiiginal will be pleasant to him. No other sense, such 20 as taste or touch, has any resemblance to moral qualities ; in sight only there is a little, for figures are to some extent of a moral character, and [so far] all participate in the feeling about them. Again, figures and colours are not imitations, 21 but signs of moral habits, and these signs occur only when the body is under the influence of emotions. The connexion of them with morals is slight, but in so far as there is any, young men should be taught to look, not at the works of Pauson, but at those of Polygnotus \ or any other painter or statuary who expresses moral ideas. On the other hand, 22 even in mere melodies ^ there is an imitation of character, for the musical modes differ essentially from one another, and those who hear them are differently affected by each. 1340 b Some of them make men sad and grave, like the so-called Mixolydian, others enfeeble the mind, like the relaxed harmonies, others, again, produce a moderate and settled temper, which aj^pears to be the peculiar effect of the Dorian ; 23 the Phrygian inspires enthusiasm. The whole subject has been well treated by philosoiihical writers on this branch of education, and they confirm their arguments by facts. The same principles apjily to ihythms ^ : some have a character of rest, others of motion, and of these latter again, 24 some have a more vulgar, others a nobler movement. Enough has been said to show that music has a power of forming the , character, and should therefoie be introduced into the education 25'of the young. The study is suited to the stage of youth, for young persons will not, if they can help, endure anything which is not sweetened by pleasuie, and music has a natural sweet- 1 Cp. Poet. 2. § 2; 6. § 15. ^ Cp. Plato, Rep. iii. 39S, 399. ' Rep. iii. 399 E, 400. The Harmonies 311 ness. There seems to be in us a sort of affinity to harmonies VIII. 5 and rhythms, which makes some philosophers say that the soul is a harmony, others, that she possesses harmony. And now we have to determine the question which 6 has been already raised \ whether children should be themselves taught to sing and play or not. Clearly there is a considerable difference made in the character by the actual practice of the ait. It is difficult, if not impossible, for those who do not perform to be good judges of the perform- \ ance of others ^. Besides, children should have something a to do, and the rattle of Archytas, which people give to their children in order to amuse them and prevent them from breaking anything in the house, was a capital invention, for a young thing cannot be quiet. The rattle is a toy suited to the infant mind, and [musical] education is a rattle or toy for children of a larger gi owth. We conclude then that they 3 should be taught music in such a way as to become not only i critics but performers. ' The question what is or is not suitable for different ages may be easily answered ; nor is there any difficulty in meeting the objection of those who say that the study of music is vulgar. We reply (i) in the first place, that they 4 who are to be judges must also be performers, and that they should begin to practise early, although when they are older they may be spared the execution ; they must have learned to appreciate what is good and to delight in it, thanks to the knowledge which they acquired in their youth. As to 5 (2) the vulgarizing effect which music is supposed to exercise, this is a question [of degree], which we shall have no difficulty in determining, when we have considered to what ' <^- 5- §§ 5-8. * Cp. supra, c 5. § 7. 312 The Gentleman Musician VIII. 6 extent freemen who are being trained to political virtue should pursue the art, what melodies and what rhythms they 13il a should be allowed to use, and what instruments should be employed in teaching them to play, for even the instrument 6 makes a difference. The answer to the objection turns upon these distinctions ; for it is quite possible that certain methods I of teaching and learning music do really have a degrading I effect. It is evident then that the learning of music ought not to impede the business of riper years, or to degrade the body or render it unfit for civil or military duties, whether for the early practice or for the later study of them. 7 The right measure will be attained if students of music stop short of the arts which are practised in professional contests, and do not seek to acquire those fantastic marvels of execution which are now the fashion in such contests, and from these 8 have passed into education. Let the young pursue their studies until they are able to feel delight in noble melodies and rhythms, and not merely in that common part of music in which every slave or child and even some animals find pleasure. From these principles we may also infer what instruments 9 should be used. The flute, or any other instrument which requires great skill, as for example the harp, ought not to hs i admitted into education, but only such as will make intelligent stuHents of music or of the other parts of education. Besides, the flute is not an instrument which has a good moral effect; it is too exciting. The proper time for using it is when the performance aims not at instruction, but at the relief loof the passions ^ And there is a further objection; the impediment which the flute presents to the use of the voice detracts from its educational value. The ancients therefore ' Cp. c. 7. § 3. Musical Instruments 313 were right in forbidding the flute to youths and freemen, VTII. 6 although they had once allowed it. For when their wealth gave u them greater leisure, and they had loftier notions of excellence, being also elated with their success, both before and after the Persian War, with more zeal than discernment they pursued every kind of knowledge, and so they introduced the flute into education. At Lacedaemon there was a Choragus who led la the Chorus with a flute, and at Athens the instrument became so popular that most freemen could play upon it. The popularity is shown by the tablet which Thrasippus dedicated when he furnished the Chorus to Ecphantides. Later expe- rience enabled men to judge what was or what was not really conducive to virtue, and they rejected both the flute and several 13 other old-fashioned instruments, such as the Lydian harp, the many-stringed lyre, the 'heptagon,' 'triangle,' ' sambuca,' and 1341 b the like — which are intended only to give pleasure to the hearer, and require extraordinary skill of hand ^ There is a meaning also in the myth of the ancients, which tells how Athene invented the flute and then threw it away. It was 14 not a bad idea of theirs, that the Goddess disliked the instrument because it made the face ugly ; but with still more reason may we say that she rejected it because the acquirement I of flute-playing contributes nothing to the mind, since toj Athene we ascribe knowledge and art. Accordingly we reject the professional instruments and alsO:i5 the professional mode of education in music — and by pro-j fessional we mean that which is adopted in contests, for in this the performer practises the art, not for the sake of his own improvement, but in order to give pleasure, and that of a vulgar sort, to his hearers. For this reason the execution of such • Cp. Plato, Rep. iii. 399 D. 314 The Professional Musician VIII. 6 music is not the part of a freeman but of a paid performer, and 1 6 the result is that the performers are vulgarized, for the end at which they aim is bad^. The vulgarity of the spectator tends to lower the character of the music and therefore of the per- formers ; they look to him — he makes them what they are, and fashions even their bodies by the movements which he expects them to exhibit. 7 We have also to consider rhythms and harmonies. Shall we use them all in education or make a distinction ? and shall the distinction be that which is made by those who are engaged in education, or shall it be some other ? For we see that music is produced by melody and rhythm, and we ought to know what influence these have respectively on education, and whether we should prefer excellence in melody or excellence in 2 rhythm. But as the subject has been veiy well treated by many musicians of the present day, and also by philosophers who have had considerable experience of musical education, to these we would refer the more exact student of the subject ; we shall only speak of it now after the manner of the legislator, having regard to general principles. 3 We accept the division of melodies proposed by certain philosophers into ethical melodies, melodiesof action, and passionate or inspiring melodies, each having, as they say, a mode or harmony corresponding to it. But we maintain further that music should be studied, not for the sake of one, but of many benefits, that is to say, with a view to (l) education, (2) purgation (the word ' purgation ' we use at present without explanation, but when hereafter we speak of poetry ^^ we will treat the subject with more precision) ; music may also J- Cp. I'lato, Laws, iii. "joo. ' Cp. Poet. c. 6, though tlie promise is really uiifulfilled. The Power of Music 315" serve (3) for intellectual enjoyment, for relaxation and for VIII. 7 recreation after exertion. It is clear, therefore, that all the 1342a harmonies must be employed by us, but not all of them in the same manner. In education ethical melodies are to be preferred, but we may listen to the melodies of action and passion whenj they are performed by others. For feelings such as pity and 14 fear, or, again, enthusiasm, exist very strongly in some souls, and have more or less influence over all. Some persons fall into a religious frenzy, whom we see disenthralled by the use of mystic melodies, which bring healing and purgation to the soul. Those who are influenced by pity or fear and every emotional 5 nature have a like experience, others in their degree are stirred by something wliich specially affects them, and all are in a manner purged and their souls lightened and delighted. The melodies of puigation likewise give an innocent pleasure to [ mankind. Such are the harmonies and the melodies in which 5 those who perform music at the theatre should be invited to compete. But since the spectators are of two kinds — the one free and educated, and the other a vulgar crowd composed of mechanics, labourers and the like — there ought to be 7 contests and exhibitions instituted for the relaxation of the second class also. And the melodies will correspond to their minds ; for as their minds are perverted fiom the natural state, so there are exaggerated and corrupted harmonies which are in like manner a perversion. A man receives pleasure fiom what is natural to him, and therefore professional musicians may be allowed to practise this lower sort of music before an audience of a lower type. But, for the purpose of education, g as I have already said, those modes and melodies should be employed which are ethical, such as the Dorian ; though we may include any others which are approved by philosophers ^i6 The Dorian, Phrygian, VIII. 7 who have had a musical education. The Socrates of the 9 Republic ' is wrong in retaining only the Phrygian mode along 1342 b with the Dorian, and tlie more so because he rejects the flute ; for the Phrygian is to the modes what the flute is to musical instruments— both of them are exciting and emotional. 10 Poetry proves this, for Bacchic frenzy and all similar emotions are most suitably expressed by the flute, and are better set to the Phrygian than to any other harmony. The dithyramb, for 11 example, is acknowledged to be Phrygian, a fact of which the connoisseurs of music offer many proofs, saying, among other things, that Philoxenus, having attempted to compose his Tales '^ as a dithyramb in the Dorian mode, found it impossible, 12 and fell back into the more appropriate Phrygian. All men ^ agree that the Dorian music is the giavest and manliest. And whereas we say that the extremes should be avoided and the mean followed, and whereas the Dorian is a mean between the other harmonies [the Phrygian and the Lydian °], it is evident that our youth should be taught the Dorian music. 13 Two principles have to be kept in view — what is possible, what is becoming : at these every man ought to aim. But even these are relative to age ; the old, who have lost their powers, cannot very well sing the severe melodies, and nature herself seems to suggest that their songs should be of the 14 more relaxed kind. Wherefore the musicians likewise blame Socrates, and with justice, for rejecting the relaxed harmonies in education under the idea that they are intoxicating ; not in the ordinary sense of intoxication (for wine rather tends to excite men), but because they have no strength in them. And so * Plato, Rep. iii. 399. ^ Retaining the MS. reading ^vQovs. Cp. Poet. c. 2. § 7» 3 Cp. c. 5. § 22. and Lydian Modes 317 with a view to a time of life when men begin to grow old, VIII. 7 they ought to practise the gentler harmonies and melodies as I well as the others. And if there be any harmony, such as the 15 Lydian above all others appears to be, which is suited to children of tender age, and possesses the elements both of order and of education, clearly [we ought to use it, for] education should be based upon three principles — the mean, the possible, the becoming, these three. , .^ . ';//x //;/,,, ^^-' INDEX Abydos, v. 6, §§ 6, 13. Account, power of calling magis- trates to, in Sparta exercised by the Ephors, ii. 9, § 26; given by Solon to the people, ib. 12, § 5; iii. II, § 8; and justly claimed by them, iii. 11 ; when exercised by all, a mark of democracy, iv. 14, §§ 4-6 ; vi. 2, § 5 ; 4^ § 5- Achaea [in Peloponnerus], v. 3, § II. Achaea [PthiotisT, ii. 9, § 3. Achaeans, the (in Colchis), viii. 4, § 3- Achilles, iii. 5, § 9. Acquisition, the art of, (i) the natural,!. ^, %\2; 11, §§1,2; includes war [in certain cases] and hunting, i. 7, § 5 ; 8, § 12 ; vii. 14, § 21 ; a part of house- hold management, i. 4, § i ; 8, §§ 13-15; 9. §§ 1-8; io> §§ 1-4; II, § 2; has a limit, ib. 8, §14; 9, §§13-18: {\\)that which is contrary to nature, in- cluding {a) exchange which goes beyond the need of life, i. 9, §§ 2-5; 10, §4; II, §3; {h} usury, ib. 10, § 4 ; 1 1, § 3 ; {c) trade, ib. 9, §4; 10, §4; II, § 3 ; {d) service for hire, ib. II, §3: (iii) the intermediate kind, ib. § 4. Adamas, v. 10, § 18. Admiral, office of (at Sparta), ii-9. §33- Aegina, iv. 4, § 21 ; v. 6, § 9. Aenos, in Thrace, v. 10, § iS. Aesymnetes, the, or dictators of ancient Hellas, iii. 14, §§8-io, 14; iv. 10, § 2 ; always received a guard, iii. 15, § 16. Agamemnon, iii. 5, §9; 14, § 4; 16, § 10. Agesilaus, King of Sparta, v. 7, §3- Agriculture, the employment fol- lowed by the greater part of mankind, i. 8, § 7; works upon, ib. II, §7; ancient legislation to encourage, vi. 4, §i S-io. Alcaeus, iii. 14, § 10. Alcyone, mother of Diodes the Corinthian, ii. 12, § 8. Aleuadae, the, at Larissa, v. 6, §13. Aliens, resident, how distin- guished from citizens, iii. i, § 4; obliged to have a patron, ib. ; enrolled by Cleisthenes in the tribes, ib. 2, §3; admitted to citizenship at Syracuse, v. 3, §13- Alliance, an, how different from a state, ii. 2, § 3 ; iii. 9, §§ 6-8. Almsgiving, demoralizing effects of, vi. 5, § 7_. Alternation in office, character- istic of constitutional govern- ments, i. I, § 2 ; 12, § 2; ii. 2, §§4-7; iii. 4, §§ 10, 14-17; 6, §§9, 10; 16, §§2, 3; 17, §4; vi. 2, §§ 2,5; vii. 14, §§ 1-5. Amadocus (? king of the Odry- sians), v. 10, § 24. Amasis, king of Egypt, i. 12, § 2. Ambition, a cause of crime, ii. 7, 320 Index §§ 10-14, 18 ; 9, § 28 ; encour- aged by the Spartan law-giver, ib. 9, § 28; a motive of revolu- tions, ii. 7, §§ 10, 18 ; V. 7, § 4; 10, § 5. Ambracia, v. 3, § 10; 4, § 9; 10, §16. Amphipolis, v. 3, § 13; 6, § 8. Amyntas the Little (? father of Philip), V. lo, § 16. Anaxilaus, tyranny of, at Rhe- gium, V. 12, § 13. Andria, ancient name of the common meals at Sparta, ii. 10, §5- Androdamas, of Rhegium, ii. 12, §14- Andros, ii. 9, § 20. Animals, the, intention of Nature in denying speech to, i. 2,§§ 10- 12 ; under the dominion of man, ib. 5, § 7 ; tame better than wild, ib. ; only difter from slaves in not being able to apprehend reason, ib. § 9 ; their various modes of life, ib. 8, §§ 4-6; supply their offspring with food in different ways, ib. § 10; cre- ated for the sake of man. ib. §§9-12; produce offspring re- sembling their parents, ii. 3, § (); cannot form a state, iii. 9, § 6 ; lead a life of nature, not of reason, vii. 13, § 12; the parts of animals an illustration of the parts of the state, iv. 4, §§ 7-9 ; the offspring of young animals often small and ill-developed, vii. 16, § 6. Antileon, tyrant at Chalcis, v. 1 2, § 12. Aiitimenides, brother of Alcaeus, iii. 14, § 9. Antissa, in Lesbos, v. 3, § 12. Antisthenes, iii. 13, § 14. Aphytaeans, the (in Pallene), vi. 4, § 10. ApollodorusofLemnos, 1. 11, §7. ApoUonia (on the Adriatic), iv. 4, §5- Apollonia (on the Euxine), v. 3, § 13; ib. 6, §9. Appeal, a court of, allowed by Hippodamus, ii. 8, § 4. Appetitive principle, the, of the soul, i.5, §6; iii. 4, §6; 16, §5; vii. 15, §§ 9, 10. Arbitrator, the judge should not be made into an, ii. 8, § 13; the middle class the arbitrators of the state, iv. 12, § 5. Arcadia, ii. 2, § 3; ib. 9, §§ 3, 11. Archelaus, king of Macedonia, V. ID, §§ 17-20. Archias of Thebes, v. 6, § 15. Archilochus, quoted, vii. 7, § 6. Archons, the duties of, vi. 8, § 20 ; the single Archon at Epidam- nus, iii. 16, § i ; v. i, § 12. Archytas, of Tarentum, viii. 6, §2. Areopagus, the, at Athens {see Council of Areopagus). Argo, the, iii. 13, § 16. Argos, use of ostracism at, v. 3, § 3 ; the political changes after ' Hebdome,' ib. 3, § 7 ! the oli- garchical revolution after the battle of Mantinea, ib. 4, § 9 ; the tyranny of Pheidon, ib. 10, § 6 ; enmity of the ArgiiJes to the Lacedaemonians, ii. 9, §§ 3, II. Ariobarzanes, v. 10, § 25. Aristocracy, characterized by election for merit, ii. 11, §§9, 1 1 ; iv. 8, § 7 ; v. 7, § i ; dis- tinguished from the perfect state, as being a government of men who are only good relatively to the constitution, iv. 7, § 2 {but cp. iii. 4, § 5) ; so called because the be?t rule or the best interests of the state are consulted, iii. 7, Index 321 § 3; not a perversion, iv. 8, § i ; analogous to oligarchy (i) be- cause the few rule, v. 7, § i ; (2) because birth and education commonly accompany wealth, iv. 8, § 3; — to royalty as a government of the best, ib. 10, § 2 ; preferable to royalty, be- cause the good are more than one, iii. 15, § 10; how distin- guished from oligarchy and constitutional government, iv. 7 ; 8; 14, § 10; v. 7, §§5-9(cp. ii. ii> §§5-10); usually degener- ates into oligarchy, iii. 7, § 5 ; 15, §11 ; iv. 2, §2; V. 7, § 7; 8, § 7 ; — causes of revolutions in aristocracies, v. 7 ; the means of their preservation, ib. 8, §§ 5-7; aristocracy less stable than con- stitutional government, ib. 7, § 6 ; liable to danger because the rich have too much power, ib. 12, §6; might be combined with democracy if the magi- strates were unpaid and office open to all, ib. S, § 17 (cp. vi. 4, § 6) ; — magistracies peculiar to aristocracy, iv. 15, § 10; vi. 8, §§22, 24; aristocratical modes of appointing magistrates and judges, iv. 15, §§ 20, 21 ; 16, §8; practice of trying all suits by the same magistrates, aristocratical, ii. 11, § 8; iii. i, § 10;— the people naturally suited to an ariiitocracy, iii. 17, §§ 3-7. Aristogeiton, conspiracy of Har- modius and, v. 10, § 15. Aristophanes, ii. 4, § 6. Arrhibaeus, king of the Lyn- cestians, v. 10, § 17. Art, works of, wherein different from realities, iii. 11, § 4. Artapanes, v. 10, § 21. Artisan, the employments of the, devoid of moral excellence, i. 13, §§13,14; iii. 5, §5; vi.4, §12; vii. 9, §§ 3, 7 ; artisans some- times public slaves, ii. 7, § 22 ; only admitted to office in de- mocracies, iii. 4, § 12; often acquire wealth, ib. 5, § 6 ; the question whether they are citi- zens, ib. 5 ; necessary to the existence of the state, iv. 4, §§ 9, 21 ; not a part of the state, vii. 4, § 6 ; should be debarred from the 'Freemen's Agora,' ib. 12, §3. Arts, the, require instruments, both living and lifeless, i. 4; some arts subservient to others, ib. 8, § 2 ; 10, §§ 1-4; the arts have a limit in their means though not in their end, ib. 8, § 14 ; 9, § 13 ; both the means and the end ought to be within our control, vii. 13, § 2 ; amount of knowledge which a freeman is permitted in the arts, i. 11, § i; viii. 2, § 5; degrees of ex- cellence in them, i. 11, §6; viii. 2j §§5,6; changes in, advan- tageous, ii. 8, § 18 ; iii. 15, § 4 ; the analogy of, not to be ex- tended to the laws, ii. 8, § 24 ; iii. 15, §4; exist for the benefit of those under tliein, iii. 6, §§ 7- 9 ; by whom should the artist be judged? ib. 11, §§ 10-14 (cp. viii. 6, §§ 1-4) ; the arts aim at some good, iii. 12, §1; justice of the different claims to political superiority illustrated from the arts, ib. 12, §§4-8; law of pro- portion in the arts, ib. 13, § 21 ; the problems of the arts, an illustration of the problems ot politics, iv. I, §§ T-4; the arts have to supply the deficiencies of Nature, vii. 17, § 15. Asia, ii. 10, § 3 ; iv. 3, § 3 ; the Asiatics better fitted for slavery 322 Index than the Hellenes, iii. 14, § 6 ; vii. 7, § 2 ; cannibal tribes in Asia, viii. 4, § 3. A.ssembly, the, payment of, evil effectsof the practice, ii. 7, § 19; iv. 6, § 5 ; vi. 2, § 6 ; how they may be counteracted, vi. 5, § 5; — power monopolized by, in ex- treme democracies, iv. 6, § 5 ; 14. §7; V. 5, §10; 6, §17; 9, § 14; vi. 2, § 5 ; 4, § 15 (cp. ii, 12, §4;v. ii,§§ii,i2); meet- ings should be infrequent, vi. 5, § 5 (cp. iv. 14, §§4, 5); charac- ter of, in the different kinds of democracies, iv. 14, §§ 4-7 ; vi. 2> §§ 5-7; in oligarchies, iv. 14, §§ 8-1 1 (cp. iii. I, § 10); pro- vision in case of equal voting in assemblies, vi. 3, § 6 : — at Car- thage, ii. II, §§ 5-6; in Crete, ib. 10, § 7 ; II, § 6 ; at Sparta, ib. II, §6. Astyages, v. 10, § 24. Atarneus (in Mysia), ii. 7, § 17. Athene, viii. 6, § 13. Athens; payment of the dicas- teries commenced by Pericles, ii. 12, §4 (cp. iv. 6, § 5; vi. 2, § 6) ; evil effects of the practice, ii. 7, §19; plan introduced by Diophantus for the regulation of the public slaves, ib. § 23 ; maintenance at the public ex- pense of the children of citizens who had fallen in battle, ib. 8, § 6 ; the Solonian constitution, ib. 7, § 6; 12, §§ 1-6; iii. 11, § 8 ; the Areopagus i^see Council of Areopagus) ; the Court of Phreatto, iv. 16, §3; effect of the Persian war upon Athens, ii. 12, §5 ; V. 4, § 8 ; viii. 6, § 11 ; introduction of flute-playing at Athens after the Persian war, viii. 6, § 1 1 ; the legislation of Draco, ii. 12, § 13; the expulsion of the tyrants, iii. 2, § 3; v. 12, § 5 ; the use of ostracism, v. 3, § 3 (cp. iii. 13, § 15); number of sailors in the population, iv. 4, § 21 ; new citizens introduced by Cleisthenes, iii. 2, § 3; the tribes redivided by him, vi. 4, § 17; treatment of the subject cities by Athens, iii. 1 3 , § 1 9 ; democrati- cal governments forced upon the allies by the Athenians, iv. 11, § 18 ; V. 7, § 14 ; great losses of the nobility in the Peloponnesian War, V. 3, § 7 ; difference of sen- timent between the Athenians and the citizens of the Piraeus, ib. § 15; origin of the war be- tween Athens and Mitylene, ib. 4, § 6 ; defeat of the Athenian expedition to Sicily, ib. § 9 ; government of the Four Hun- dred, ib. § 13 ; 6, § 6; of the Thirty, ib. 6, § 6 ; rise of Pei- sistratus to the tyranny, ib.5, §9; 10, § 6 ; his trial before the Areopagus, ib. 12, § 2; con- spiracy of Harmodius and Aris- togeiton, ib. 10, § 15 ; magistracy of the Eleven, vi. 8, § 11. Athlete, the temperament of an, not suited to the life of tiie citizen, vii. 16, § 12; viii. 4. Athletics : see Gymnastic Exer- cises. Attalus, v. 10, § 16. Ausones, the, or Opici, vii. 10, §.^- Autophradates, satrap of Lydia, ii. 7> § 17- Avarice, encouraged at Sparta, ii. 9, §§ 13, 28, 37; at Carthage, ib. II, §11; a frequent cause of crime, ib. 7, § 19; 9, § 28 ; of revolution, v. 2, § 5 ; 3, §1. Babylonia, ii. 6, §6; Babylon, iii. 3, §5; BabyloiiianSjib.ig, §19. Index 323 Bacchiadae.the, at Corinth, ii. 12, Barbarians, the, do not distin- guish the female and the slave, i. 2, §4; generally under kingly rule, ib. §6 (cp. iii. 14, §6); regarded by the Hellenes as natural slaves, i. 6, § 6 ; their nobility not recognized by the Hellenes, ib. § 7; prevalence of barter among them, ib. 8, § 5. Barter : see Exchange. Basilidae, the, v. 6, § 5. Bequest, freedom of, at Sparta, ii. 9, § 14; should be forbidden by law, V. 8, § 20. Birth, illegitimate, not a dis- qualification for citizenship in extreme democracies, iii. 5, § 7 ; vi. 4, §16. Blest,theIslandsofthe,vii.i5,§4. Body, the, ruled according to nature by the soul, i. 5, §§ 4-7 ; the body of the freeman not always distinguished by nature from that of the slave, ib. § 10; the beauty of the body more obvious than that of the soul, ib. §11; the interest of, identi- cal with that of the soul, ib. 6, § 10; the goods of, for the sake of the soul, vii. i, §§8, 9; prior to the soul, ib. 15, § 10; must not be educated at the same time as the mind, viii. 3, § 13 ; 4, §9- Body, habit of, to be required in the citizen, vii. 16, § 12 ; viii. 3, §13- Byzantium, iv. 4, § 2 1 ; v. 3, § 1 2. Camicus, ii. 10, § 4. Carthage, the constitution of, analogous to those of Lacedae- mon and Crete, ii. 1 1, §§ i, 5 ; an aristocracy with oligarchical and democratical features, ib. §§5-10; iv.7, §4; V. 12, §14; never had a revolution, ii. ri, §§ 2, 15 ; y. 12, § 14; never under a tyranny, ii. 11, § 2 {but cp.v. 12, § 12); the kingspartly chosen for ability, ii. 11, §§4-9; influence of wealth, ib. §§ 9-13; plurality of offices, ib. § 13 ; the magistrates judges in crim- inal cases, ib. § 7 ; iii. i, §§ 10, II ; honours paid to military merit, vii. 2, § 10; the con- spiracy of Hanno, v. 7, § 4 ; custom of sending out the poorer citizens to the colonies, ii. II, § 15 ; vi. 5, § 9 ; treaties between the Carthaginians and the Tyrrhenians, iii. 9, § 6. Catana, ii. 12, § 6. Cavalry, importance of, in the ancient oligarchies, iv. 3, §3; 13, § 10; vi. 7, § I (cp. the government of ' the knights ' in E etria, v. 6, § 14). Celts, the, ii. 9, § 7; vii. 2, § 10; 17, §3; Chalcidian cities, the (in Italy and Sicily), ii. 12, § 6 ; — (of Thrace), ib. § 14. Chalcis, in Euboea, iv. 3, § 3; v. 4, §9; ib. 12, § 12. Chares, the Athenian general, V. 6, § 9. — of Paros, a writer on Agri- culture, i. II, § 7. Charicles, leader of a party among the Thirty at Athens, V. 6, § 6. Charilaus, king of Sparta, ii. 10, § 2; V. 12, § 12. Charondas, used the word ofj-o- a'nrvoi for the members of a family, i. 2, §5; legislated for Catana and the other Chalcidian cities in Italy and Sicily, ii. 12, § 6 ; said to have been the disciple of Zaleucus, ib. § 7 ; 3 24 Index the first to make laws a_c;ainst perjury, ib. § 1 1 ; famous for the accuracy of his legislation, ib. ; belonged to the middle class, iv. 1 1, § 15 ; compelled the rich to attend the law-courts, ib. 13, §2. Child, the, relation of, and the parent, i. 2, § 2 ; 3, § 1 ; the virtue of, ib. 13, §§ 3-12; ruled like a king by the elder or parent, ib. 2, §6; 7, § i ; 12, § 3; has the deliberative faculty, but immature, ib. 13, §7 (^cp. vii. 15, § lo)- Children, ought to be educated with regard to the constitution, i. 13, § 15; V. 9, §§ 11-15; viii. I ; recognized in certain coun- tries by their resemblance to their parents, ii. 3, § 9 ; the children of citizens who died in battle reared at the public ex- pense, ib. 8, §6; children, in what sense citizens, iii. i, § 5 ; 5, § 2 ; education of the chil- dren of kings, ib. 4, § 8 ; bad education of the children of the rich, iv. 11, §§ 4-S; v. 9, §§ ii- 15 ; licence permitted to chil- dren in democracies and tyran- nies, vi. 4, § 20 ; exposure of deformed children, vii. 16, § 15; way in which children should be reared, ib. 17 ; they should not see or hear anything indecent, ib. §§ 7-11; viii. 5, §§ 19-21 ; what their education should include, viii. 2 ; 3 ; why they ought to learn music and draw- ing, ib. 3, § 2 foil. ; degree to which they should carry musical proficiency, ib. 6, §§ 1-8; must not carry gymnastic exercise too far, il). 4 ; must not labour with body and mind at once, ib. § 9; restlessness of young children, ib. 6, § 2 ; their toys. ib. ; their crying not to be checked, vii. 17' §6. Children, Plato's community of, see Women and Children. Children, Guardians of, iv. 15, §§9, 13; vi. 8, § 22. Chios, iii. 13, § 19; iv. 4, § 21 ; V. 3, § 12 ; 6, § 16. Chones, the, in southern Italy, vii. 10, § 5. Chytrum, a part of Clazomenae, Cinadon, v. 7, § 3. Citizen, the, must both rule and obey, i. I, § 2 ; 12, § 2; ii. 2, §§4-7; II, § 14; iii. 4, §§ 10- 16; 5. §1 ; 6, §§9-ii; 13, § 12; 16, §§ 2, 3; 17, § 4; vi. 2, § 5 ; vii. 9, §§4-8; 14, §§ 1-8 ; must have leisure, ii. 9, § 2; II, §§ 10, 12; vii. 9, §§ 4, 7; 12, §7; belongs to the state, viii. I , § 4 ; — necessity of defining the word, iii. i, § 2 foil. ; children and old men, in what sense citizens, ib. § 5 ; 5, § 2 ; resi- dence and legal rights, inade- quate definitions, ib. I, §§ 4, 5; not enough that the parents were citizens, ib. 2, §§ 1-3 ; the citizen must share in the ad- ministration of the state, ib. i, §§5-12; 2, §§3-5; 5; 13, § 12; differs under each form of gov- ernineat, ib. i, § 9 ; 5, § 5 ; 13. §12; iv. 7, § 2 ; the question about citizens admitted after a revolution, iii. 2, §§ 3-5 ; — the virtue of the good citizen : is it identical with that of the good man ? ib. 4 ; 5 , § 10 ; 1 8 ; vii. 14, § 8, the virtue of the citizen in the perfect state, iii. 4, § 5 ; 13, § 12 ; — not all citizens who are necessary to the state, ib. 5, §2; vii. 9, §10; the artisans Index 325- not to be citizens, iii. 5 ; vii. 9, §3; nor the sailors, vii. 6, §§ 7, 8 ; is the life of the citizen the best ? ib. 2 ; 3 ; the character necessary in the citizens, ib. 7 ! their habit of body, ib. 16, § 12; viii. 3, § 13; 4- Citizenship, rights of, conferred on strangers in early times at Sparta, ii.9, § 17 ; lost at Sparta, by failure to contribute to the common meals, ib. § 32 ; 10, § 7 ; given to persons of ille- gitimate birth in extreme de- mocracies, iii. 5, § 7; vi. 4, § 16; exclusion from, sometimes con- cealed, iii. 6, §9; easily pre- tended in a large state, vii. 4, § 14- City, the : see State. Clazomenae, v. 3, § 15. Cleander, tyrant of Gela, v. 12, § 13- Cleisthenes, tyrant of Sicyon, v. 12, §§i, 12. — , the Athenian, iii. 2. § 3 ; vi. 4, § 18. Cleomenes (king of Sparta), v. 3, §7. Cleopatra (the widow of Perdic- cas), V. 10, § 17- Cleotimus, leader of a revolution at Amphipolis, v. 6, § 8. Clubs; at Carthage, ii. ir, §3; at Abydos, v. 6, §§ 6, 13; hated by tyrants, ii. 11, § 5. Cnidus, V. 6, §§ 4, 16. Codrus, king of Athens, v. to, § 8. Colonies, of Carthage, ii. it, § 15; vi. 5, § 9 ; oligai chies formed in colonies by the first settlers, iv. 4, § s ; dissensions in, a cause of revolutions, v. 3, §§ 11-14. Colophon, of, iv. 4, § 5 ; v. 3, §15- Commerce, divisions of, i. ti , § 3 ; its advantages and disadvan- tages, vii. 6 ; — commercial trea- ties, iii. 9, § 6. Common meals, hostility of the tyrant to, v. 11 , § 5 ; first estab- lished in Italy, vii, 10, §§ 1-8; how they should be arranged, ib. §§ 10-12 ; the young not allowed to share in them, ib. 1 7, § II ; — of the magistrates, vi. 2, § 7 ; vii. 12, § I ; of the priests, vii. 12, §6; — (at Carthage), ii. II; § 3;— (in Crete), ib. 5, §15; the original of the Spartan, ib. 10, § 5 ; maintained at the public cost, ib. §§7-10; — (at Sparta), make property to some degree common, ib. 5, § 15; badly regu- lated, ib. 9, §§31, 32; TO, § 7; anciently called ' andria,' ib. 10, §5. Community of women and chil- dren, the, proposed by Plato, ii. I, § 3; arguments against, ii. 3 ; 4 ; — of property, ib. 5 ; vii. 10, §9. Confederacy, difference between a, and a state, ii. 2, § 3; iii. 9, §§ 6-8. Constitution, regard must be had to the, in education, i. 13, § 15; v. 9, §§ 11-15; viii. I ; the best constitution supposed by some to be a combination of all exist- ing forms, ii. 6, § 17 (cp. iv. i, §6; 7, § 4; 9. § 7); the per- manence of a constitution only secured by the consent of all classes, ii.9, §22; iv. 9, §10; 12, §6; v. 8, §5; 9, §§ 5-10; vi. 6, § 2; 7, § 4; older constitu- tions more simple than later, ii. 10, § i; contentment with a constitution not always a proof of its excellence, ib. 10, § 12 {but cp. c. II, §§ 2, 15) ; in each constitution the citizen differ- ent, iii. I, §9; 5, § 5; 13, §12; 32<^ hidex iv. 7, § 2; relation of the con- stitution and the state, iii. i, § i; 3. §9; 6, § i; 7> § 2; iv. i, §10; 3. §5; definition of the word, iii. i, §1; 6, §1; iv. i, §10; 3, §5; the constitution the life of the state, iv. 11, § 3; the people naturally suited to each constitution, iii. 17; the constitution sometimes nomin- ally unchanged after a revolu- tion, iv. 5, §§3,4(cp.v. I, §8); the encroachments of the rich often more dangerous to the constitution than those of the poor, iv. 12, § 6; life according to the constitution no slavery, V. 9> § 15;. vii. 5, §§ 1-3- Corinth, iii. 9, § 9; tyranny of Timophanes, v. 6, § 12 ; tyranny of the Cypselids, ib. ID, § 6; 11, §9; its duration, ib. I 2, §§ 3, 4; family of the Bacchiadae, ii. 1 2, §8. Cos, v. 5, § 2. Cosmi, the (in Crete), to the Ephors, ii. 10, §§6-14. Cotys, king of the Odrysians in Thrace, v. 10, § 18. Council of Areopagus, the, ii. 1 2, §§ 2, 4; V. 4, § 8; 12, § 2. Councillors and warriors, the two highest classes in the stale, iv. 4, §§10-17; vii. 4, §§4-7; 8, §7; 9, §§ 4-10. Crataeus, one of the assassins of Archelaus, v. 10, § 17. Crete, favourable position of, ii. lOj §§ 3, 12, 16; visit of Lycurgiis to,ib. § 2 ; — the Cretan constitu- tion the original of the Lace- daemonian, ib. §§ 1-3; analo- gous to the Carthaginian, ib. 1 1, § I ; the attention of the legis- lator diiected solely to war, vii. 2, § 9 ; — the common tables in- troduced into Crete by Minos, ib. 10, §§2,6; called by the Cretans, dvSpia, ii. 10, § 5 ; ob- ject of the institution, ii. 5, §15; better managed in Crete than at Lacedaemon, ib. 9, §§30-33; io> §§ 7-9;— frequency of sedi- tion in Crete, ib. 10, §§ I4, 15 ; — slaves in Crete forbidden gymnastic exercises and the use of arms, ib. 5, § 19; thePerioeci in Crete well managed, ib. 9, § 3; 10, §§ 15, 16 ; governed by the laws of Minos, ib. 10, §3; ana- logy of the Cretan Perioeci with the Helots, ib. § 5 ; — existence of caste in Crete, vii. 10, § 1. Custom, power of, ii. 8, § 24; iv. 5. §3; vii. 13, §§ 11-13; a sort of justice, i. 6, § 5. Cyclopes, the, i. 2, § 7. Cyme, in Aeolis, v. 5, § 4. Cypselids, the, v. 11, §9; ib. 12, §§3,4- Cypselus of Corinth, v. 10, § 6 ; 12, § 3. Cyrcne, vi. 4, §§ 17, 18. Cyrus, king of Persia, v. 10, §§8,24. Daedalus, i. 4, § 3. Dancing, viii. 5, § 3. Daphnaeus, of Syracuse, v. 5, § 10. Darius, son of Xerxes, v. 10, § 21. Decamnichus, v. 10, § 20. Deliberation, the right to share in, essential to the citizen, iii. i ; §§6-12 ; 2, § 5; 13, § 12 (cp. vii. S, § 7). Delphi, v. 4, § 5 ; the Delphian knife, i. 2, § 3. Dcniagoguts, the authors and flatterers of the extreme demo- cracy, ii. 12, §§ 4-6; iv. 4, §§ 25-31; V.9, § 10; II, §§ II, 12; vi. 4, §§ 15-17; wnfiscate Index 327 the property of the rich, v. 5, § 5; vi. 5, §3; often bring about revolutions, v. 3, § 4; 5, §§ 1-5; in ancient times became tyrants, ib. 5, §§ 6-10; io,§§4, 6: — in oligarchies, ib. 6, § 5. Demiurgi, magistrates atLarissa, iii. 2, § 2. Democracy, the government of the many in their own interests, iii. 7, § 5; 8, § 2; iv. II, § 17; akin to tyranny, iv. 4, § 27; v. ID, §§ 11,30, 35; II, §12; the only possible government in large states, iii. 15, § 12; iv. 6, §5; 13. § 10 (cp- vi. 5, § 5); the perversion of constitutional government, iii. 7, §5; iv. 2, §§ I, 2; Plato wrong in calling democracy the worst of good constitutions, but the best of bad ones, iv. 2, § 3 ; insuffici- ency of the common definitions of democracy, iii. 8; iv. 4, §§ I- 6; more forms of democracy than one, iv. i, § 8 ; 4, §§ 20- 22; II, § 20; 12, § 3; 13, § 12; vi. I, § 2 ; the forms enumerated, iv. 4, §§ 22-31; 6, §§1-7; 12, §3; 14, §§ 1-7; vi. 4; growth ot the last and worst form, ii. 12, §4; iii. 4, § 12; 6, §§9-11; iv. 6, §5; v. 5, §§6-ii; 6, §§6-8; 9, § 10; vi. 2, §§5-9; 4, §§ i5-2o(cp. V. 10, § 12; II, § 11); — democracy more stable than oligarchy, iv. n, § 14; v. I, §15; 7, §6 (cp. v. 3, §8); causes of revolution in democra- cies : anarchy, v. 3, § 5 ; vi. 4, § 17 ; demagogic practices, v. 3. §4; 5 ; 9, § i.o; vi. 5, §5; disproportionate increase, v. 3, §§ 6-8 ; dissatisfaction of the notables, ib. § I4(cp.ii. 7, §§ 10, 18) ; long tenure or greatness of office, V. 5, § 8 ; 8, '§ 7 ; the means of their preservation, iv. 12, §4; 13, §§ 5-8; 14, §12 ; v. 8 ; vi. 4, § 1 7 ; 5 ; democracy (especially the extreme form) apt to pass into tyranny, iv. 11, § 11; V. 5, §§6-io; 8, §7; ID, §30; Plato censured for supposing that the change is necessarily to tyranny, v. 12, § 10 ; — Athens the champion of democracy in Hellas, iv. 11, § 18 ; V. 7, § 14; the democratic principle represented at Sparta by the Ephoralty, ii. 6, § 17 ; 9, § 21; 10, §10; iv. 9, §9; — characteristics of democracy : liberty and equality for all, iii. 8, § 7 ; iv. 4. §§22, 23; 8, §7; V. I, § 3; 8, §6; 9, §§14, 15; vi. 2, §§ 1-4, 9; 4, § 20; the use of the lot, ii. 11, §7; 12, § 3 ; iv. 9, §4; 15, § 19; vi. 2. §§5, 8 ; employment of a large number of magistrates, ii. 11, § 14 ; short tenure of office, v. 8, § 6; vi. 2, §§5, 8 ; pay- ment of the citizens, ii. 7, § 19; 12, §4; iv. 6, § 5; 9, § 2; vi. 2>§§6, 7; 5, §6; carelessness in the admission of artisans and persons of illegitimate birth to citizenship, iii. 4, § 12 ; 5, §§7, 8; vi. 4, § 16; licence allowed to women and children, v- 11, §11; vi. 4, § 20 ; — ostracism oiiginally a democratic institu- tion, iii. 13, § 15; V. 3, § 3; democratical tricks to keep the power in the hands of the people, iv. 13, §5 ; suggestions for the improvement of demo- cracy, ib. 14, § 12; vi. 5, §§5- II ; the magistrates peculiar to democracy, iv. 15, § 11 ; vi. 8, §§ 17, 24; democratical modes of appointing magistrates and judges, iv. 15, § 19; 16, § 8 ; — 328 Index character and powers of the assembly, ib. 14, §§ 1-7 ;— the best material of a democracy, ib. 6, § 2 ; vi. 4, § i ; the position suitable to a democracy, vii. II, §5; democracy always supported by the sailors and light armed, vi. 7, §§ i, 2. Dcrdas (? King of Elymaea), v. 10, § 16. Devices, political, of oligarchies and democracies, iv. 13, §§ I- S ; their inutility, v. 8, § 4. Diagoras, an Eretrian, v. 6, § I4. Dicaea, 'the Pharsalian mare,' ii- 3, § 9- Dicasteries, the Athenian, ii. 12, §4- Dictators : see Aesymnetes. Diodes, ii. 12, §§8-ii. Dion, V. 10, §§ 23, 28, 31, 32. Dionysius the Elder, i. 11, §§ii, 12; iii. 15, §16; V. 5, §§8, 10; 7, § 10 ; 10, § 6 ; II, § 10. Dionysius the Younger, v. 10, §§23, 28, 31, 32. Diophantus, ii. 7, § 23. Directors of Education, vii. 1 7, §§5) 7 ; of Gymnastics, vi. 8, § 22. Dorian Harmony, the : see Harmony. Dowries, ii. 7, § 3 ; 9, § 15. Doxander, v. 4, § 6. Draco, ii. 12, § i.^. Drawing, a branch of education, viii. 3, §§ I, 12. Dynasty, or Family Oligarchy : see Oligarchy. Ecphantides (the ancient comic poet), viii. 6, § 12. Education, may be directed to a wrong end, ii. 7, §§ 8, 9; must have regard to the constitution, i. 13, § 15; v. 9, §11; viii. I ; the great means of uniting the state, ii. 5, §§ 18- 21 ; special, for the ruler, iii. 4, §8 (cp. vii. 14, § 6) ; confers a claim to pre-eminence in the state, iii. 13, § i (cp. c. 9, §§ 14, i.=i; X2, §§S, 9; iv. 8, §§2-5); excellence of the Spartan education, iv. 9, § 7 ; viii. i, §4 {but cp. viii. 4, §§1-7); bad education of the rich, iv. II, § 6 ; V. 9, § 13 ; hostility of the tyrant to education, v. 11, § 5 .; education necessary to supplement habit, vii. 13, § 13; 17, § 15 ; the special business of the legislator, viii. i, § 1 ; wrong notions of education prevalent in Hellas, vii. 14, § 15 ; viii. I, § 3 ; 4, § 6 ; the periods of education, vii. 17; viii. 4, §§7-9; liccessily of a common system of education, viii. 1, § 3 (cp. ii. 7, § 8 ; and iv. 9, § 7) ; should education have an ethical or a practical aim ? viii. 2 ; 3 ; 5; should it include music? ib. 3 ; 5 > 6 ; what instruments and harmonies are to be used ? ib. 6, §§8-i6; 7; education not to be directed to a single end, ib. 4, § 2 ; the proper place of gymnastics in education, ib. 3,§i3; 4; the education of mind and body not to be carried on togetlKT, ib. 4, § 9 ; writers upon musical education, ib. 5, § 23; 7, §§ 2, 3, 8, II, 14; musical education a kind of rattle to older children, ib. 6, § 2 ; the three principles of edu- cation, ib. 7, § 15 : — Directors of Education, vii. 17, §§ 5, 7. Egypt, iii. 15, §4; v. 11, §9; vii. 10, §§ 1-6, 8. I'^evenjthe, at Athens, vi. 8, § 11. Elis, V. 6, § II. Elymaea, v. 10, § 17. Index 329 Empire, unnecessary to the hap- piness of states, vii. 2:3; 14, §§ 12-22. End, the, the completed nature of each thing, i. 2, § 8 ; has no limit in the arts, ib. 8, § 14 ; 9, § 13 ; may agree or disagree with the means, vii. 13, § 2 ; contains an element of pleasure, viii. 5, § 13- Ephialtes, ii. 12, §4. Ephors, the, a democratic element at Sparta, ii. 6, § 17 ; 9, §§ 20- 22; 10, §10; iv. 9, §9; their corruption and licence, ii. 9, §§19-24; 10, §12; greatness of their power, ib. 9, § 20 ; v. II, § 2 ; the mode of their election childish, ii. 9, §23; have the right of calling the magistrates to account, ib. § 26; try suits respecting contracts, iii. I, § 10 (cp. ii. 9, § 23 ; 11, § 7) ; established by Theopom- pus as a check on the royal power, V. II, §§ 1-3 ; corre- spond to the Cosmi in Crete, ii. 10, §§ 6, 10, 12; to the magis- tracy of 104 at Carthage, ib. 11. §3. Epidamnus, ii. 7, § 23 ; iii. 16, §1; V. I, §§ 10, II ; 4, §7. Epimenides, of Crete, i. 2, §5. Equality, how related to justice, iii. 9; 12 ; 13, §§ II, 12 ; v. I, § 2 ; 9, §14; vii. 3, §5; 14. §§ 1-6 ; (the true kind) no longer desired in Hellenic states, iv. 11, §§4-10, 19; v, 9> §§5-10; equality and liberty the aim of democracy, iii. 8, § 7 ; iv. 4, § 22; 8, §7; V. I, §3; 8. §6; 9' §14; vi. 2, §§i- 4, 9 ; the desire of equality a cause of sedition, v. i, §§ 3-8 ; 2) §§2, 3; 3, § 2 ; when attained creates contentment, ib. 7, § 6 ; equality either numerical or proportional, iii. 8; iv. 12, §§ 1-4; V. I, §§ 12- 16 ; vi. 3 ; states must not be based on one kind alone, v. i, § 14 ; denied to the weak by the strong, vi. 3, § 6. Equality of property, proposed by Phaleas, ii. 7 ; 12, § 12. Eretria, iv. 3j § 3 ; v. 6, § 14. Erythrae, v. 6, § 5. Ethiopia, iv. 4, § 4. Eubulus (tyrant of Atarneus), ii. 7. §17- Euripides, v, 10, § 20 ; quoted, i. 2, § 4 ; iii. 4,! § § ! v. 9, § 15; vii. 7, § 8 ; viii. 5, § 2. Europe, vii. 7, § 2. Euryphon, ii. 8, § i. Eurytion, v. 6, § 15. Euthyciates, aPhocian, V. 4, §7. Evngoras, tyrant of Salamis in Cyprus, v. 10, § 16. Evil, i. 2, § 12. Exchange, (i) according to nature (barter of necessaries), i- 9. §§ 2-7; 10, §§3, 4; (2) contrary to nature (retail trade), i. 9, §§ 1-4, 9-12 ; 10, §4; II, §3. Executive element, the, in the state, iv. 14, § 2 ; 15 ; vi. 8. Experience, value of, ii. 5, § 16 ; vii. 10, § 8. Exposure of deformed children, justifiable, vii. 16, § 15. Extremes, danger of, iv. 11, §§16-19; 12, §§4-6; vi. 5, §§ 1-4- Faction, frequency of, in Crete, ii. 10, §§ 14-16 ; evil effects of, in Hellas, iv. 11, §§ 16-1 S; a cause of revolution in oligar- chies, V. 6, § 9 ; less common in democracies, iv. ii, § 14; v. I, §§ 15. '6; 1, §6. 330 Index Family, the, the villa^^e a colony of, i. 2, § 6 ; (cp. c. 9, § 5) ; composed of three relations which are sanctioned by nature, ib. 3, § 2 foil. ; 3, §§1-3; 12; 13. § 15 j governed by the elder or parent who is their king, ib. 2, §6; 7, § I ; 12, §3; different kinds of rule within the family, ib. 12 ; the family apart of the state, ib. 13, § 15; ii. 9, §5; the state more self sufficient than the family, ii. 2, § 8. Family oligarchy : 55^ Oligarchy. Family quarrels, a cause of revolutions, v. 4, §§ 5-7 ; 6, § 14; 10. § .^■ Father and child, relation of, i. 2, §§ 1-5; 3. §§ 1-3; 12- Female, the, by nature different from the slave except among barbarians, i. 2, §§3,4; subject by nature to the male, ib. 5, § 7; 12, § i; 13, §7; tendency of the female to produce off- spring like the parents, ii. 3, § 9 :— the union of mr.le and female formed in obedience to a natural in.=tinct, i. 2, § 2 ; the relation of male and female part of the household, ib. 3, § 2 ; 12, § I. {See Woman.] Finance, importance of, to the statesman, i. 11, §13; the finances of Sparta badly man- aged, ii. 9, § 36 ; sugt;estions for the regulation of state finances, v. 8, §§ 15-19; vi. 5. Four Hundred, government of the, at Athens, v. 4, § 13 ; 6, § 6. Freedom, supposed by Hellenes not to exist among barbarians, i. 2, § 4 ; 6, § 6 ; is a reason why men claim authority in a slate, iii. 9, § 14 ; 12, § 8; 13, §§ 2-5. [i"£« Liberty.] Freeman, the, i:i Ids relation to the slave, i. 2, §§ 2-4 ; 3, § 4; 5 ; 6 ; not always outwardly distinguished by nature from him, ib. 5, § 10 ; rule over freemen more noble than rule over slaves, ib. § 2 ; vii. 3, § 2 ; 14, §19; will never willingly submit to the tyrant, iv. 10, § 4 ; V. II, § 12 ; has a natural right to rule, ii. 2, § 6 ; iii. 16, §§2,3 ; must not be ashamed to obey his lawful superiors, v. 9, §§ 11-14; vii. 3, § 2; 14, §§ 1-5 (cp. iv. II, § 6); may have a certain knowledc;e of the arts, viii. 2, §§ 5, 6 ; may be al- lowed to share in the pleasures of music, ib. 5, § 7. Friendship, weakened by com- munism, ii. 4, §§ 5-9 ; the motive of society, ib. § 6 ; iii. 9, §13; iv. II, §7 (cp. vi. 5, §§7-11); implies equality, iii. 16, § 13 ; friendship among the citizens hated by the tyrant, v. II, § 5 ; friendship at Sparta, ii- 5. § 7- Gela, v. 12, § 13. Gelo, tyrant of Syracuse, v, 3, §5 ; 10, §31; 12, §§5,6. General, the, learns command by obedience, iii. 4, § 14 ; generals often became dcmaijogues in an- cient times, V. 5, §§ 6-10 ; have often attacked their masters, ib. 10, § 24 ; wise generals com- bine light-armed troops with cavalry and heavy infantry, vi. 7, § 2. _ Generalship, a rare quality, v. 9, § 3- Gerusia : see Council of Elders. God, happy by reason of his own nature, vii. 1, §10; 3, § 10 ; alone able to hold together the universe, ib. 4, § 8. Index 331 Gods, the, supposed to be under a king because mankind origin- ally were, i. 2, § 7 ; 12, § 3; their statues more beautiful than ordinary human forms, ib. 5,§ 10. Good, absolute and relative, vii. 13, §§5-8. Good, the, the aim of the state, i. I, § I ; ii. 2, § 7. Good and evil, the sense of, cha- racteristic of man, i. 2, §12; made the test of freedom and slavery, ib. 6, § 8. Goods, the three kinds of, vii. i, §§ 2-5 ; external goods not to be preferred to virtue, ii. 9, §35; vii. 1, §§5-9; 15, §6; not the cause of happiness, vii. I, § 10; 13, §8. Gordius, father of Psammetichus, tyrant of Corinth, v. 12, § 3. Gorgias of Leontini, i. 13, § 10 ; iii. 2, § 2. Government, the Constitutional, called in ancient times demo- cracy, iv. 1 3, § 1 1 ; its rarity, ib. 7, § I (cp. c. II, § 16) ; one of the true forms of government, i''- 7» § 3 (cp- iv. 8, § i) ; liow distinguished from aristocracy, oligarchy, and democracy, iv. 7; 8; 14, §§8-io; V. 7, §§5-7; vi. I, §3 (cp. ii. 11, §§5-9); composed of the heavy-armed soldiers, ii. 6, § 16 ; iii. 7, § 4 ; 17, §4; iv. 13, §10; the people to whom it is adapted, iii. 17, § 4 ; suited to a large country population, vi. 4, §14; cha- racterized by the alternation of rulers and ruled, i. i, §2 ; 12, § 2; ii. 2, §§4-7; II, § 14; iii. 4, §§ 10, 14; 6, §9 ; 16, § 2; 17, §4; vii. 14, §§ 1-5 (cp. i. 7, § i); by the combination of thevoteand thelot intheelection ol the magistrates, iv. 15, §§19- 22 ; gives the affirmative power to the many, ib. 14, § 16 ; the mode in which it arises, ib. 9 ; causes of revolution to which it is subject, v. 3, §§ 6-8 ; 6, §§ 16-1S ; 7, §§ 5-9 ; means of its preservation, ib. 8, §§ ic, 1 1 ; more stable than aristocracy, ib. 7, §6. Government, forms of, how to be criticized, ii. 9, § i ; iv. i ; the legislator must know all, iv. 1, §§ 5-8 ; differ according to the character of the supreme authority, iii. 6, § i ; 13, § 5 ; iv. 8, §§ 2-4; 14, § I ; are based on partial justice only, iii. 9, §§ 1-4, 15 ; 17, §6; V. 1, §2; vi. 3, §§1-4; are all perversions of the perfect state, iv. 8, §1 ; may be divided into true forms or perversions, iii. I, §§8-io ; 6, § II ; 7 ; 18; iv. 2, §§ 1-3; 8, § I ; their suc- cessive changes in ancient times, iii. 15, §§ 11-13; iv. 13, §§9- 12 ; Plato's theory of change wrong, V. 12, §§5-18 ; influence of increased population upon forms of government, iii. 15, §§ 11-13; iv. 6, §5; vi.5,§5; the worst forms the most pre- carious, vi. 6, § 4 ; common error that forms of government can be reduced to two — oli- garchy and democracy, iv. 3, §§6-8 ; sense in which this is true, ib. 4, § 19; v. i, § 14 (cp. vi. I, § 6) ; the people adapted to each form of government, iii. 1 7 ; the magistrates suited to each, iv. 15, §§ 11-13 ; vi. 8, §§17, 24; thejudicial arrange- ments, ii. II, § 7 ; iii. i, §§ 10, 11; iv. 16, §8; the mihtary force, vi. 7, §§ 1 , 2. Government, writers on, often un- 332 Index practical, iv. i, § 5; have ex- tolled the Lacedaemonian con- stitution, ib. §6; vii. 14, §§ 16, 17. Guardians, the, in Plato's Republic : see Plato. Gymnastic, like other arts, has undergone improvement, ii. 8, §18; includes various kinds of training, iv. i, §§ i, 2. Gymnastic exercises, forbidden to slaves in Crete, ii. 5, § 19; discouraged in oligarchies among <;he poor, iv. 1 3, § 4 ; one of the recognized branches of education, viii. 3, § i ; carried to excess at Lacedaemon, ib. 4, §§1-7; suggestions for their arrangement, vii. 12, §§1-6; should be of a lighter kind for children, viii. 4, § 7 : — Directors of, vi. 8, § 22. Habit, the strength of law derived from, ii. 8, §24; one element of virtue, vii. 13, §§ 11-13 ; 15. § 7 ; must go before reason in education, viii. 3, § 13. Hanno, v. 7, § 4. Happiness, independent of exter- nal goods, vii. I, § 10 ; 13, §8; the happiness of the v/hole de- pendent on the happiness of the parts, i. 6, §10; ii. 5, 627; vii. 9, § 7 ; hajjpiness propor- tioned to virtue, vii. i, § 10; 8, §5; 9. §§.^' 7; I.-.. §5; the perfect happiness of the divine nature, ib, I, § 10; 3, §10; the happiness of men and states the same, ib. 2 ; 3 ; the happiness of states not dependent on em- pire over others, ib. 2, §§ 14-18; or on size. ib. 4, §§4-1 1 ; hajipi- ness imjilies virtuous activity, ib. 3, §§ 1-3 ; is the worthy employment of leisure, viii. 3, §§ 3-6 ; 5. §§ 9-15- Harbours, should be separated from the city, vii. 6, §§ i-6. Harmodius, v. 10, § 15. Harmonies, the, iv. 3, § 7 ; viii. 5, §§ 16-25 ; 7- Harmony, the soul said to be, or lo possess, viii. 5, § 25. Harmony, the Dorian, iii. 3, §8 ; iv. 3, § 7 ; produces a moderate and settled temper, viii. 5, § 22 ; 7> §§8-13: — the Lydian ; re- jected by Plato in the Republic, ib- 7, §§ 9, 14; suitable to children, ib. § 15 :— the Mixo- Lydian ; has a sad and grave effect, ib. 5, § 22 : — the Phry- gian, iii. 3, § 8 ; iv. 3, § 7 ; inspires enthusiasm , viii. 5 , § 2 2 ; 7, § 9 ; should not have been retained by Plato, ib. 7,§§9-i3. Ilebdome, v. 3, § 7. Ileliaea, court of, at Epidamnus, V. I, § J I. Hellanocrates of Larissa, v. 10, § iS. Hellas, influence of the climate of, on the national character, vii. 7, ^ij 1-4; natural superi- ority of Hellenes to Barbarians, i. 2, §4; 6, §6; iii. 14, § 6; vii- 7> § 3 ; differences of the various Hellenic tribes, vii. 7, § 4 : — barl.'arous laws among the ancient Hellenes, ii. 8, § 20; the Hellenes formerly under royal rule, i. 2 , § 6 ; iii. 1 5 , § 1 1 . iv. 13, § 10; changes in govern- ment caused by the increase of population, iii. 15, §§ 11-13; iv. 6, §5;. 13, §§ 10-12 ; vi- 5, § 5 ; rise of the heavy-armed in importance, iv. 13, §10; effects of the Persian war upon Hellas, ii. 12, § 5 ; v. 4, § 8 ; viii. 6, § II ; growth of the Athenian empire in Hellas, iii. 'Sj § 19 i division of Hellas be- Index 333 tween Athens and Lacedaemon, iv. II, § i8; V. 7, § 14:— smallness of the middle class in later Hellas, iv. 11, §§7, 16- 19; lack of great men, v. 10, § 37 ; effects of the cultivation of rhetoric, ib. 5, §7; wrong notions of education, i v. 11, § 6 ; vii. 14, § 15 ; viii. i, § 3 ; 2, § 2 : — rage for flute playing in Hellas after the Persian War, viii. 6, § 12. Helots, ii. 5, §2259, § 2 ; 10, §§4, i6- Heniochi, the, in Pontus, viii. 4, §3- Hephaestus, i. 4, § 3. Heraclea, in Pontus, v. 5, § 3 ; 6, §§2,3, 7, 15; vii. 6, §8. Heracleidesof Aenos,v. 10, § 18. Heracleitus, v. ir, § 31. Heracleodorus, v. 3, § 9. Heracles, iii. 13, § 16. Heraea (in Arcadia), v. 3, § g. Hesiod,quoted,i.2,§5; v.io,§3o. Hestiaea (the later Oreus) in Eu- boea, V. 3, § 9 ; 4, § 4. Hiero, tyrant of Syracuse, v. 10, §31; II, § 7; 12, §§5,6. Hipparinus, v. 6, § 8. Hippocrates, vii. 4, § 5. Hippodamus, of Miletus, ii. 8, § I ; vii. II, §6. Homer, calls Zeus ' the father of Gods and men,' i. 12, §2; — quoted, II. ii. 204 ; iv. 4, § 27 ; ib. 372 ; iii. 16, § 10 ; v. 391-3; ib. 14, §6; ix. 63; i. 2, § 9; ib. 319 ; ii. 7, § 10; ib. 648 ; iii. 5, § 9; X. 224 ; ib. 16, § 10 ; xviii. 376 ; i. 4. § 3 ; Odyss. ix. 7 ; viii. 3, § 9 ; ib. 14; i. 2, §7; xvii. 385 ; viii. 3, § 9 : — a passage is also cited, viii. 3, § 8, which does not occur in our Homer. Honour, inequality in, a cause of revolutions, ii. 7, §§ 10-13, ^8- 20 ; v. 2, § 2 ; 3, §§ 2, 14; 4, §§ 8-10 ; 12, § 18 ; the remedy for this, V. 8, § 12; 11, §§26, 27 ; the citizen must share in the honours of the state, iii. 5, §9 (cp.c. 10, §§4, 5); honour less desired by men than wealth, iv. I3,§8; V. 8, § 16; vi. 4, §3 (cp. vi. 7, § 7). Household management, the art of, distinguished from the rule of a master, i, i, §253, § 4 ; 7, § I ; iii. 6, §§6, 7; divided into three parts, i. 3, §§ 1-3 : 12, § I ; how related to money- making, ib. 3, §3; 8, §§ I, 2 ; 9, §§ I, 12-18 ; 10, §§ 1-4 ; includes the natural art of ac- quisition, ib. 4, § 1 ; 8, §§ IS- IS ; 9> §§ 1-8; 10, §§1-4; II, §§1-3; has a limit, ib. 9,. §§14, 18; is more concerned with virtue than with wealth, ib. 13, § I ; the parts of men and women in, different, iii. 4. §17; exists for the benefit of those under it, ib. 6, §§6, 7. Husband and wife, relation of. l^See ' Male ' and ' Female.'] Husbandmen, are sometimes hunters, i. 8, § 8 ; would be better suited for Plato's com- munism than the guardians, ii. 4, § 4; make the best form of democracy, iv. 6, § 2 ; 12, § 3 ; vi. 4, §§ I, 8-10 ; furnish good sailors, vii. 6, § 8 ; should not be citizens, ib. 9, § 8 ; 10, §5 13, 14 ; nor admitted to office, ib. 9, § 9 ; should be excluded from the 'Freemen'sAgora,'ib.i2,§3. Husbandry, a part of the natural 334 Index art of money-making, i. 8, § 3 ; 10, § 3; II, § 2. lapygia, v. 3, § 7 ; vii. 10, § 5. Iberians, the, vii. 2, §11. India, vii. 14, § 3. Inheritance, sale ofan, forbidden, ii- 7. § 6 ; (at Sparla\ ib. 9, § 14 (cp. V. 8, § 20) ; the divi- sion of an, may be a cause of revolution, v. 4, § 4. Instruments, best when made for one use, i. 2, § 3; may be either living or lifeless, ib. 4, § 2 ; are used either in production or in action, ib. §§4-6; are never unlimited in the arts, ib. 8, §§14, 15 ; the slave a living instrument, ib. 4, §§2, 6. Ionia, V. 10, § 6. Ionian Gulf, the, vii. 10, § 5. Iphiades, a party leader at Abydos, v. 6, § 14. Istros, V. 6, § 2. Italus, king of Oenotria, vii. 10, §3- Italy, >ii. 10, §§ 2-6. Jason, tyrant of Pherae,iii. 4, §9. Judges, not allowed to commu- nicate with each other, ii. 8, §13; should not hold office for life, ib. 9, § 25 ; necessary, even in the first beginnings of the state, iv. 4, §§13, 14; }he various modes of appointing them, ib. 16, §§ 5-7 ; provision for an equal division of opinion among judges, vi. 3, § 6 ; those who inflict penalties to be different from those who see to their execution, ib. 8, §§8-11. Justice, the sense of, peculiar to man, i. 2, §12; the bond of men in states, ib. § 16 ; iii. 12, §9; i,^. §3; (cp. iv. 4, § 13); sometimes defined as benevo- lence, i. 6, §4; different in men and women, ib. 13, §§ 3, 9 ; in the ruler and the subject, ib. §§2-8; iii. 4, §§ 16-18; con- sists in equality, iii. 9, § i ; 12, § i; 13, § 12 ; vii. 14, § 3 ; cannot be the destruction of the state, iii. 10, § 2 ; cannot be united with the love of conquest, vii. 2, §§ 7-18 ; selfishness of the ordinary notions of justice, vi. 3, §6; vii. 2, § 14; all claims to rule based upon partial and relative justice only, iii. 9, §§ 1-6, 15; V- I, §§2-6 ; 9, § i; vi. 2, § 2; 3, §§ 1-4. King, the, not the same with the statesman, i. I, § 2 ; ought to be chosen for merit (as at Carthage), ii. 9, § 29 ; 11, §4; receives a special education, iii. 4, § 8 ; may be justified in put- ting down his rivals, ib. 13^^ § 22 ; v. II, § 27 ; is the champion of the better classes against the people, v. 10, § 3 ; often supreme in religions matters, iii. 14, §13; vi. 8, § 20 ; should behave a military force? iii. 15, §§14-16; is guarded by the citizens, ib. 14, § 7 ; v. 10, § 10. King, the true, or natural supe- rior of the citizens, iii. 13, §§ 13, 24, 25; 17, §§5-8 ; vii. 3, § 6 ; unknown in later Hellas, V. 10, § 37. {See Royalty.] King, a, the Gods why supposed to be under, i. 2, § 7 ; 12, § 3. Kings, the, of Crete (in ancient times), ii. 10, §6; of Carthage, ib. II, §§ 3-6, 9, 10 ; of Mace- donia, V. 10, §8; of the Molos- sians, ib. ; 11, § 2 ; of Persia, viii. 5, § 5 ; of Sparta [je^ Lace- daemon] : — Kings, the ancient, Lidex 337 sometimes became tyrants, v. 10, § 5. Kniglits, the, at Athens, ii. 12, § 6; at Eretria, v. 6, § 14. Lacedaemon ; frequent wars of the Lacedaemonians with their neighbours, ii. 9, §§ 3, 11 ; their difdcnlties with the Helots, ib. §§ 2-4 (cp. ib. 5, § 22) ; the Messenian Wars, ib. § ii ; v. 7> §§3. 4 ) tlie conspiracy of the Partheniae, v. 7, § 2 ; — of Pausanias, ib. i, § 10; 7, §4; vii. 14, § 20; — ofCinadon,v. 7, § 3 ; — of Lysander, ib. i, §10; 7, § 2 ; the putting down of the tyrants, ib. 10, § 30; the subject cities governed in the oligar- chical interest by tke Lacedae- monians, iv. II, § 18; V. 7, § 14 ; — friendship among the Lacedaemonians, ii. 5, § 7 ; agiiculture forbidden to them, lb. §17; simplicity of life among them, 113.6, § 17 ; iv. 9, §§ 6-9; excellence of the Lacedae- monian education, iv. 9, § 7 ; viii. I, §4 '^bui cp. vii. 2, § 9 ; viii. 4, § 1) ; music not com- prised in it, viii. 5, § 7 ; Lace- daemonian training only ad- vantageous while other nations did not train, ib. 4, §§ 4-7 ; rage for flute-playing at Lace- daemon after the Persian War, ib. 6, § 1 2 ; error of the Lace- daemonians in thinking the ob- jects of their desire preferable to the virtue which gained them, ii. 9> §35 (cp. vii. i,§5); spirit of distrust in the Lacedaemonian government, ii. 9, § 30 ; bad management of the revenue, ib. § 36 ; frequency of corruption, ib. §§19, 26; 10, §12; accu- mulation of property, ib. 9, §§ 13. 14; V. 7.-§§ 3, io(cp. V, 12, § 15) ; number of heiresses, ii. 9, § 15 ; decrease in popu- lation, ib. §§ 14-19; encourage- ment of large families, ib. § 14; expulsion of strangers, ib. 10, § 15 ; strangers admitted to citizenship in ancient times, ib. 9, § 17; licence of the Lacedae- monian women, ib. §§ 5-13 : — the Lacedaemonian constitution a combination of various lonns of government, ib. 6, §§ ]6, 17; 9, § 22 ; — an aristocracy with an element of democracy, iv. 7, § 4 (cp. ii. 9, § 20 ; 10, § 10) ; — re- garded by some as a democracy, by others as an oligarchy, iv. 9, §§6-io; — often considered the next best to the ideal state, ii. 6, § 16 ; iv. I, § 6 ; — its resem- blance to the Cretan, ii. 10, §§4-7;— to the Carthaginian, ib. II, §§3-5 ; the arrangement of the law-courts at Lacedaemon, an aristocratical feature, ib. § 7 ; iii. I, §§ 10, 11; the attention of the legislator directed solely to war, ii. 9, §§ 34, 35 ; vii. 2, §9; 14, §§ 16-22 ; viii. 4, §§ 1-7 : — imperfections of the Lacedaemonian monarchy, ii. 9, §§29,30; II, §§ 3, 4; limited powers of the kings, iii. 14, § 3 ; V. 1 1 , § 2 ; their office an heredi- tary generalship, ii. 9, § 33 ; iii. 14, §§4, 5, 14 ; 15, §§ 1,2 ; 16, § I : origin of their power, V. ID, § 8 ; reason of its long continuance, ib. 11, §2: — the Gerusia criticized, ii, 9, §§ 25- 29; II, §§4, II ; V. 6, § II : — faults and merits of the Epho- ralty, ii. 6, § 17; 9, §§ 19-24, 26 ; 10, §§ 10, 12 ; II, § 3; established by Theopompus as a check on the royal power, v. 33^ Index II) § § 2 , 3 ; — the office of ad- miial, ii. 9, § 3.^ : — the com- mon tables, why instituted, ib. 5, § 15: 6, § 17; 9, §§ 31,32 ; iv. 9, § 8 ; not so well managed as in Crete, ii. 9, § 32 ; 10, §§7.8- Lametic Gnlf, the, vii. 10, § 3. Land, the, should be divided into two portions, vii. 10, § 11 {but cp. ii. 6, § 15) : Hippodamus's division of, ii. 8, §§3, 12; — should it be cultivated by the owners? ib. 5, §§3, 18, 19; 8, §§8-13; vii. 9, §§1-4; 10, §§ 13, 14; at Sparta, had fallen into the hands of a few, ii. 9, §§i4> ^5- Landowners, small, to be encour- aged, vi. 4, §§ 8-10.' Larissa, iii. 2, § 2 ; v. 6, §§ 6, 13. Law, the, of Oxylus, vi. 4, § 9: — Laws, the, ol Androdamas, ii. 12, § 14; of Charondas, ib. §§ 6-8, II ; iv. 13, § 2 ; of Draco, ii. 12, §13; ofLycuigus (j'ffi Sparta) ; of Minos, ii. 10, § 3 ; vii. 10, § I ; of Phaleas, ii, 7 ; 12, § T2 ; of Philolaus, ib. 12, §§8-io; of Pittacus, ib. § 13 ; of Plato {see Plato) ; of Solon, ii. 7, § 6 ; 1 2, §§ 1-6 ; iii. II, §8; of Zaleucus, ii. 12, §6. Law, the, derives its force from habit, ii. 8, § 24 ; 'a surety of justice' (Lycophron), iii. 9, § 8 ; may have a party character, ib. 10, §5; II, §20; only exists for equals, ib. 13, §§13, 14; 16, §§2, 3 ; must be supported by force in the ruler, ib. 15, §§ 14, 15 ; is a mean, ib. 16, § 8 ; is order, vii. 4, § 8 ; is without passion, iii. 15, § 5 ; the rule of, the rule of God, ib. 16, §5 (cp. i. 2, §§15, 16);- should the law or the monarch rule? iii. 15, §§i-io; 16; — should the law ever be changed ? ii. 8, §§ 16-25 (cp. iii. 15, §§6, 7; 16, § 5) : — Laws, the, cannot provide for circumstances, ii. 8. § 22; iii. II, § 19; 15, §§4-8 ; 16, §§4-13; should be sui>reme, and the magistrates only their interpreters, iii. 11, §19; 16, §§ 5, 10-12 ; iv. 4, § 31 ; are relative to the constitution, but distinct from it, iii. 11, § 20 ; iv. I, §§9, 10; must be obeyed and must be good, iv. 4, § 30 ; 8, §§.=;, 6. Law, the, or convention, by which prisoners of war become slaves, i- 6, §§ I, 5- Law, unwritten, importance of, iii. i6, § 9. Laws, the, of Hellenic citiesgene- rally in a chaotic state, vii. 2,§ 9. Laws, the, of Plato {see Plato). Law Courts, the, oligarchical and democratical tricks with, iv. 9, § 2 ; 13, §§2, 5 ; 14, § 12; the rich should beencour- aged to attend, even in demo- cracies, vi. 5, § 5 ; used by the demagogues to ruin the rich, v. 3, § 4; .5, §§ i-.S ; vi. 5, §3- Law courts, the possible varieties of, iv. 16. Legislator, the, must have regard to the country and the people, ii. 6, § 7 ; 7, §§ 14-17 ; must pay attention to the foreign re- lations of the state, ib. ; ib. ; vii. 2, § i8; must secure leisure for his citizens, ii. 9, § 2 ; 11, §§ 10, 12 ; vii. 9, §§ 3, 7 (cp. vii. 12, § 7); must not trust to accidents, ii. n, §§ 15, 17; vii. i.^! §§S-io; must regard the common good, iii. 13, § 12; ought not to want such a princi- ple as ostraci.sni, ib. § 23 ; v. 3, Index 337 §3; mnst know all possible forms of state, iv. i , § 8 ; and the causes of their preservation and destruction, V. 9, §9; vi. 5, § 2 ; must be able to reform as well as to create a state, iv. i , § 7 ; should favour the middle class, ib. 12, § 4 ; must consider the deliberative, executive, and judicial elements in relation to the constitution of each state, ib. 14, § I ; must be modest in his designs, ii. 6, § 7 ; viii. 4, § 2 ; should not make conquest the aim of his slate, vii. 2 ; must give all the citizens a share in the administration, ib. 14, § 4 ; must have a care of edu- cation, ib. §§ i, 8; 15, §8; viii. I, §§ I, 2 ; must not neglect physical education, vii. 16, § i. Legislators, the best, belonged to the middle class, iv. 11, § 15. Leisure, the, of the citizens, the first object of the legislator, ii. 9, § 2 ; II, §§ 10-12 ; vii. 9, §§3,4. 7 (cp.vii. 12, §7); the citizen must know the right uses of, vii. 14, §§ 13-22 ; viii. 3:5, § 4; needed for virtue, vii. 9, § 4. Leontini. v. 10, § 6 ; 12, § 13. Lesbos, iii. 13, § 19. Leucas, ii. 7, § 7. Liberty, supposed to be the characteristic feature of demo- cracy, iii. 8, § 7 ; iv. 4, §§ 22, 23; 8, §7; V. I, §3; 8, §6; 9, §§ 14, 15 ; vi. 2, §§ 1-4, 9 ; 4, § 20 ; must not be confused with licence, v. 9, § 15 ; — should be held out as a reward to slaves, vii. 10. § 14. Life, action, not production, i. 4, § 5 ; pleasure of, iii. 6, § 5 ; is the speculative or the practical, better? vii. 2, §§5-18; 3 :— divided by the poets into periods DAVIS of seven years, ib. x6, § 17; 17, § 15 : — simplicity of, at Sparta, ii. 6, § 17 ; iv. 9, § 7. Life, the good, not desired by mankind in general, i. 9, § 16 ; the object of the existence of the state, ib. 2, § 8 ; iii. 9, §§ 6-14; iv. 4, § 12 ; vii. i, § i ; 2, §17; 4, § 1 1 ; 8, § 4 ; is it the same for states and for individuals ? vii. I ; 2 ; 3, § 10. Limit, a, necessary in the arts, i. 8, § 14; 9. § 13; iii- 13. §21 ; vii. 4, § 10 ; in population, ii. 6, §§6, 10; 7, §5 ; 9> § 19 ; vii. 4, §§4-11; 5, §1; 16, § 15 ; in the state, ii. 6, § 7 ; iii. 3> §§4-7; vii. 4; 5, § ^ ; in wealth, j. 8, §14; 9, §14; ii. 6,§§S, 9; 7, §§4-8; vii. 5, § I. Locri (in Italy), ii. 7, § 6; 12, §6; V. 7, § 10. Lot, use of the, characteristic of democracy, ii. II, § 7; 12, §3; iv. 9, §4; 15, § 19; vi. 2, §§5, 8 ; modes in which it may be used in elections of magistrates, iv. 15, §§ 16-22. Lycophron, the Sophist, iii. 9, § ^- . Lyctus, in Crete, ii. 10, § 2. Lycurgus,the author of the Lace- daemonian constitution, ii. 10, § 2 ; 12, § I ; was the guardian of Charilaus, ib. 10, § 2 ; his visit to Crete, ib. ; his failure to bringthe women under his laws, ib. 9, § § 1 1 , 1 2 ; said by some to have been a disciple of Thales, ib. 12, §7; belonged to the middle class, iv. 11, § 15. Lydian Harmony, the : see Har- mony. Lygdamis, tyrant of Naxos, v. 6, §1. Lysander, v. i, § 10 ; 7, § 2. 338 hidex Macedonia, V. lo, §8; vii. 2,§ lo. Magistrates, power of calling to account \_see Account, power of callingmagistratestoj ; division of law-suits among the Lace- daemonians and Carthaginian magistrates, ii. ii, §7; iii. 1, § 10 (cp. iv. 14, § 3) ; election of magistrates by merit charac- teristic of aristocracy, ii. 11, §§7, 9; iv. 15, §10; — for wealth, of oligarchy, ii. 6, § 19; 11, §9 ; iv. 15, § 10; choice by lot, of democracy, ii. 6, § 19 ; 12, §3; iv. 15, § 19; vi. 2, §§ 5, 9 ; must be taken from those who carry arms, ii. 8, § 9 ; iv. 13, § 9; are very numerous in democracies, ii. 11, § 14; ought to be only the guardians and interpreters of the law, iii. ir, §19; 16, §§5, 10-12 ; iv. 4, § 31 ; character and powers of the magistrates in aristocracies, iv. 14, § 10; 15, § 13; vi. 8, § 22 ; in constitutional govern- ments, iv. 14, §§ 10, 16; in democracies, ib. §§1-7; 15, §§ 10-14; yi- 2, §§ 5-9 ; 8, §§17, 24; in oligarchies, iv. 14, §§8,9; 15, §§ 10-14; vi. 8, §§17, 24; the magistrates peculiar to each constitution, iv. 15, §§ 11-13; vi. 8, §§ 17, 24 ; definition of the term 'magis- trate,' iv. 15, §§ 1-4; should he hold more tlian one office ? ii. 11, §13; iv. 15, §§ 5-10; vi, 8, § ■: ; the various modes of appointment, iv. 15, §§ 14-21 ; vi. 5, §11; popular election dangerous, v. 5, § 10 ; 6, § 6 ; the magistrates should not be allowed to make money, ib. 3, § I ; 8, § 15 ; vi. 7, § 5 (cp. v. 12, § 14) ; undue power ac- quired by thern a cause of revo- lution, v. 3, §3; 4, §§8-ii ; great authority of the ancient magistrates, iii. 16, § i ; v. I, §10; 5, §8; 10, §5 ; vi. 2, § 8 ; the magistrates may pre- vent revolutions by prudence, v. 8, § 8 ; manner in which they should act in oligarchies, vi. 5,§§io, 11; 7, §§4-7; enume- ration of the different magis- trates required by states, vi. 8 ; the magistrates must know the characters of their fellow- citizens, vii. 4, § 13 ; must sup- press obscenity, ib. 17, § 10 : — Magistrates, certain, required by law to take their meals to- gether, vi. 2, § 7 ; vii. 12, § 2. Magnesia (on the Maeander), iv. Z, § 3- Magnesians, the, ii. 9, § 3. Majority, the (in a state), diffi- culties about the power which should be possessed by, iii. 10 ; II ; 13. §§4-7 ; vi. 3. Male and female, reason for the union of, i. 2, § 2 ; the relation of, part of the household, ib. 3, § 2 ; 12, § I. Male, the, intended by nature to rule over the female, i. 5, § 7 ; 12, §1. Malians, the, iv. 13, §9. Man a political animal, i. 2, §§9. 14, 1.5 ; iii- 6, § 3 ; has a natural wish for posterity, i. 2, § 2 ; alone has the faculty of speech, ib. § 10; — the sense of good and evil, ib. §12; — the power of reason, vii. 13, §12; the worst of animals when not controlled by law and justice, i- 2, §§ 15, 16; must allow reason to direct nature and habit, vii. 13, §§11-13; should give the soul rule over the body, '• it §§4-7; the plants and Index 339 animals created for his sake, ib. 8, § 12 : — Man, tlie virtue of the, different from that of the woman, ib. 13, §§ 3, 9-11 ; iii. 4, § 16: — Men are imlimited in their desires, i. 9, §§ i6-i8 ; ii- 7) §§8) 19; ai's wicked by nature, ii. 5, § 12; are more desirous of gain than of honour, iv. 13, §8; V. 8, § 16; vi. 4, § 3 ; are satisfied with a mode- rate amount of virtue, vii. i, § 5 : — Men, the first, were or- dinary, foolish people, ii. 8, §21. Mantinea, battle of, v. 4, § 9 ; government by representation at, vi. 4, § 4. Marriage, regulations respecting, vii. 16 ; — the marriage relation, i- 2, §2; 3, §§ 1-3; 12; iii. 4, §6. Massalia, v. 6, §§2,3; vi. 7, §4- Master, the, in relation to the slave, i. 2, §§ 2-5 ; 3, §§ 1-3 ; 12, § i; 13, §§7, 12-14 ; has a common interest with the slave, ib. 6, § 10; iii. 6, § fi ; vii. 14, § 6 ; ought to train the slave in virtue, i. 13, § 14; — the science peculiar to, ib. 3, § 4; 7, §§ 2- 5 ; 13, § 14;— the rule of, ib. 3, § 4 ; iii. 4, § 11; vii. 14, §6; wrongly supposed [by Plato] to be different from political rule, i- I, § 2 ; 3, §4- Mean, importance of the, in states, iv. 11; v. 9, § 6 ; in education, viii. 6, § 7 ; 7, § 15. Mechanic, the: see Artisan. Medes, the, iii. 13, § 19 ; viii. 5;§5- Medicine, i. 9, §§13, 17; 10, §§3, 4; ii. 8, §18. {See Physician.) Megacles, v. 10, § 19. Mcgara, iii, 9, § 9 ; iv. 15, § 15; V. 3, § 5; 5, §§4, 9- Messenian War, the (Second), v. 7, § 3- Messenians, the, ii. 9, §§ 3, 11. Metics : see Aliens. Midas, i. 9, § li. Middle class, virtues of the, iv. II; 12; the middle-class state the best, ib. 11, §§8-15; 12, § 4 ; V. 8, § 14 ; 9, § 6 ; small- ness of the middle class in ancient states, iv. 13, §11. Might and right, i. 6, § 3 ; vi. 3, §6; vii. 2, §13. Miletus, i. 1 1, § 9 ; v. 5, § 8. Minos, ii. 10, § 3; vii. 10, §§ 2, 6. Mithridates (?Satrap of Pontus), V. 10, § 25. Mitylene, iii. 14, §10; v. 4, §§5, 6 ; ID, § 19. Mixo-Lydian Harmony, the: see Harmony. Mnaseas, a Phocian, v. 4, § 7. Mnason, a Phocian, v. 4, § 7. Moderation in poliUcs, necessary for the salvation 61 the state, iv. II, §§ 16-19; V. 9. §6; vi. 5, §2. Molossians, the, in Epirus, v. 10, §8; IT, § 2. Monarchy, arguments for and against, iii. 15-17- Monarchy : see King, Royalty, and Tyranny. Money, origin of, i. 9, § 8 ; its conventional nature, ib. § 11 ; ought not to be made from money, ib. 10, § 5. Money-making, the art of, how related to household manage- ment, i. 3. § 3 ; 8, §§ I, 2 ; 9, §§ I, 12-18; ID, §§ 1-4; the natural kind, ib. 8, §§ 3-15 ; 9, §§i-8; 10, §§1-4; II, §§ I, 2; the unnatural, ib. 9, § 1 foil.; Z 2 340 Index 10, §§ 4, 5 ; II, §3; tlie inter- mediate, ib. II, §4; tile un- nntiiral pursues its end williout limit, ib. 9, §§ i.V'S- Monopolies, a common method of gaining wealth, i. 11, §§8-13. Multitude, the, their claim to the supreme power, iii. 10, § i ; are better collectively than the in- dividual, ib. II ; 13, §4; 15 ; should have power only to elect and control the magistrates, ib. 11, §7- Musaeus, quoted, viii. 5, § 11. Music, subject to a ruling princi- ple, i. 5, §4; better judged of by the many than by the indi- vidual, iii. II, §3; useful (i) in education, viii. 3; 5 ; 7) §3: (2) for the intellectual employ- ment of leisure, ib. 3 ; 5, §§ 8, 9 ; 7> § 3 ; (3) with a view to purification, ib. 7, §§ 3-6 ; has an effect upon morals, ib. 5, §§7. 15-2.5; 6, §§i, 6; 7, §§ 3-7 ; "Ot taught at Lacedae- mon, ib. 5, § 7 ; naturally plea- sant to men, ib. §§ S, 11, 25; 7, § 6 ; produces enthusiasm, ib. 5, §§ 16, 22 ; 7, § 4; allays the passions, ib. 6, § 9 ; 7' §§ 4"^ 5 a rattle for children of a larger growth, ib. 6, § 2 ; cannot be judged except by a perforijier, ib. § 4 {but cp. c. 5, § 7) ; must not be pursued to the point of professional excellence, ib. 6,§§7, 15; includes ahigher and a lower kind, ib. §8; 7, § 6 ; is composed of melody and rhythm, ib. 5, § 18 ; 6, § 5 ; 7, §>• Music, writers upon, viii. 5, § 23 ; 7. §§ 2, 3, ^\ II, 14- Musical Harmony : «« Harmony. Myron, tyrant at Sicyon, v. 12, §12. Mytilene : see Mitylene. Nature, implants in man a desire of posterity, i. 2, § 2 ; makes a distinction between the ruler and the ruled, ib. ; 4, § 6; 5 ; 6, § 8 ; 12; 13, § 4 ; — between the female and the slave, ib. 2, § 3 ; her designs must be sought in things which areuncorrupted, ib. 5, §5 ; does nothing in a niggardly fashion, ib. 2, §3; creates nothing in vain, ib. §10; 8, §12; ii. 5,§8; gives to man the social instinct, ib. 2, §§ 10- 16 ; iii. 6, §§ 3-5 ; not always able to accomplish her inten- tions, i. 5, § 10; 6, § 8 ; sup- plies food for all, ib. 8, § § 9-1 2 ; 10, § 3 ; has given all freemen a right to rule, ii. 2, §6; iii. 16, §§2, 3 ; fits the young to obey, the old to command, vii. 9, §6; permits proper relaxation, viii. 3, § 2 ; herself suggests the pro- per harmonies for each age, ib. 7, § 13 > — forms one element in virtue, vii. 13, §§ 11-13; 15. § 7 ; must be supplemented by art and education, ib. 17, § 15. Naval force, the, which should be possessed by the state, vii. 6, §§ 6-9. Naxos, v. 6, § I. Nobility, among Barbarians only partially recognized by Hellenes, i. 6,§7; confers aclaim to supe- riority in the state, iii. 9, § 15 ; 12, §9; 13. §§ 2-5; iv- 8, §3 ; may be defined (i) as excellence of race, iii. 13, §3; v. i, §7; (2) as ancient w ealth and virtue, iv. 8, § 9 ; confused by mankind with wealth, ib. §§4, 8; v. 7, § I ; like virtue, is not often tcund, v. I, § 1 4. Nobles, quarrels among, a cause Index 341 of revolutions, V. I, §16; 4, §1; 6, § 5 ; S, § 9; form a demo- cracy among themselves, ib. 8, § 6 ; should be humane to the subject classes, iv. 13, § 8; vi. 5, §§ 5-11. Notium, v. 3, §15. Obedience, the necessary prelim- inary to command, iii. 4, §§ 10, 14; vii. 9, § 6; 14, § 6. Odysseus, viii. 3, § 9. Oenophyta, battle of, v. 3, § 5. Oinotrians, the (in Southern Italy), vii. 10, §§3-5. Office, the ' indefinite, ' in which all the citizens share, iii. i, §§6-12; 2, §5. Office, lust of mankind for, iii. 6, § 10; oligarchical tiicksto keep the poor from, iv. 13. §§ 1-4; justice of the various claims to, iii. 10-13: — Offices, the, of the state, posts of honour, ib. 10, §4; their distribution, iv. 15 ; vi. 8 ; their organization deter- mines the character of each constitution, iv. i, § 10 ; 3, § 5 ; in small states must be com- bined, in large ones specialized, ii. II, §14; iv. 15, §§ 5-7 ; vi. 8, § 2 ; in democracies restricted to six months' tenure, v. 8, §6; (cp. vi. 2, § 5) ; and rarely held more than once by the same person, iii. i, § 6 ; vi. 2, § .s ; should be divided into two classes, v. 8, § 21 ; vi. 5, § 11. Offices, sale of, and pluralism, at Carthage, ii. 11, §§ 10, 13. Oligarchy, the government of the few for their private interests, iii. 6, § 2 ; 8, § 3; — or, more correctly, of the wealthv, ib. 7, § 5 ; 8, §§6, 7; iv. 4, §§i-6, 19; 8, §7 ; II, §§16-19; V. 1, §3; vi. 2, § 7; Plato wrong in think- ing that an oligarchy can ever be called 'good,' iv. 2, §3; oli- garchy the perversion of aristo- cracy, iii. 7, § 5 ; 15. § 12 ; iv. 2, § 2 ; how distinguished from it, ii. II, §§5-10; iv. 5, § i; 7; 8, §§ 2-10; 14, § 10; v. 7, §§5-8; popularly supposed, like aristocrac}', to be a 'govern- ment of the best,' iv. 8, § 4; v. I, § 14; analogous to tyranny in love of wealth, v. 10, § 11 ; has more forms than one, iv. i, § 8; 4, §§ 20-22 ; 12, § 3; 13, § 12 ; the forms enumerated, ib. 5. §§1-3; 6, §§7-n; 14, §§8-ii; vi. 6; oligarchy less stable than democracy, iv. 11, § 14; V. I, § 15; 7, § 6; the shortest lived of all forms of governments, excepting tyranny, V. 12, § I (cp. vi. 6, § 4 ) ; the extreme form apt to pass into tyranny.iv. 11, § 11 ; v. 10, § 5; 12, § 13; the causes of revo- lutions in oligarchies, v. 3, § 14 ; 6 ; 12, §§ 15-18 ; the means of their preservation, ib. 6, §9; 8> §§ 5-21 ; 9; "^i- 6, § 5 ; 7 ; — the Lacedaemonians the champions of oligarchy in Hellas, iv. 11, § iS; v. 7, § 14; — the people towliom oligarchy is suited, iv. 2, § 4; 12, § 3 ; — the military strength of oligarchy derived from cavalry and heavy infantry, ib. 3, § 3 ; 13, §10; vi. 7, § I ; — oligarchical modes of appointing magistrates and judges, ii. 6, §§ 19, 20 ; iv. 14, §§7-11; 15. §§14-21; 16, §8; magistracies peculiar to oli- garchy, iv, 14, § 14; 15, §11 ; vi. 8, §§17, 24; — luxury of the women in oligarchies, iv. 15, § 13; bad education of the children, ib. 11, §6; v. 9, 342 Index § 1 3 : — the oligarchs sometimes forbidden to engage in trade, v. 12, § 14; their tricks to keep the power in their own hands, iv. 9, § 2 ; 13, §§ 1-4; 14, §12; they ought rather to give the people a share in the go- vernment, ib. 14, §14; vi. 5, § II ; 7> § 4 > they sliould not take oaths against the people, V. 9, §§ 10, II ; they should not be allowed to make money by office, ib. 3, § i ; 8, § 15; vi. 7> § 5- Olympic Games, the, viii. 4, § 8. Olympus, melodies of, viii. 5, § 16. Onomacritus, the Locrian, ii. 12, §7. Onomarchus, a Phocian, v. 4, §7- Opici,the,orAusones,vii. 10, §5. Opus (in Locris), iii. 16, § i. Oratory, v. 5, § 7. Oreus : see Hestiaea. Orthagoras, v. 12, §1. Ostracism,howfar justiliable, iii. I3> §§13-25; 17. §7; V. 3, §3; 8, §12. Oxylus, king of Elis, vi. 4, § 9. Paches, v. 4, § 6. Painters, combine their works from scattered elements, iii. 11, § 4 ; like other artists, observe a rule of proportion, ib. 13, § 21 ; those who, like Poly- gnotus, express moral ideas, to be jireferrcd, viii. 5, § 21. Paintings, obscene, not to be al- lowed, vii. 17, § 9. Panaetius, tyrant of Leontini, v. 10, §6; 12, § 13. Parent, the, relation of, to the child, i. 2, § 2 ; 3, § 2 ; 12 ; provides food for the offspring, lb. 8, § 10; 10, § 3. Parrhon, of Aenos, v. 10, § 18. Partheniae,the (atLacedaemon), conspiracy of, v. 7, § 2. Passion, intended by nature to be controlled by reason, i. 5, § 6 ; present in the human soul from the first, iii. 15, §§5, 8 ; 16, § 5 ; vii. 15, § 10 ; blinds men to danger, v. 10, §34; 11, §31 ; the multitude freer from passion than the individual, iii. 15, § 8, Patrimony, laws forbidding the sale of a, ii. 7, § 6 ; 9, § 14 (cp. v. 8, § 20). Pausanias, the assassin of Philip of Macedon, v. 10, § 16. Pausanias, son of Cleorabrotus, incorrectly called king, v. i, §10; vii. 14, §20; his con- spiracy, V. I, § 10; 7, §4; vii. 14, § 20. Pauson, paintings of, viii. 5, §21. Payment of the democracy ; in- troduced at Athens by Pericles and Ephialtes, ii. 12, §4; Lad effects of the practice, ib. 7, § 19; iv. 6, § 5; vi. 2, § 6; how they may be counteracted, vi. .5, § 5- Peace, the true object of war, vii. 14, §§13, 22; 15, §§ I, 5; the dangers of, ib. 15, § 3. pccliaci, the (or 'men of the plain'), at Athens, v. 5, § 9. Pcisistratus, v. 5, § 9 ; 12, §§2, 5; — Peisi^ratidae, the, V. 10, §§15, 34; II, §9; 12, § 5- Peloponnesus, ii. 10, § 3; iii. 3, § 5 ; — Peloponnesian War, the : see War, Peloponnesian. Penestae, the, ii. 5, § 22 ; 9, § 2. Pentacosio-medinini, the, in .Solon's constitution, ii. 12, §6. Pcnthalidae, the, at Mitylene, v. 10, § 19. Index 343 Penthilus (? tyrant of Mitylene), V. lo, § 19. Periander, tyrant of Ambracia, V. 4, § 9 ; 10, § 16. Periander, tyrant of Corinth, iii. 13, §i6; V. 10, §13; II, § 4; 12, §3. Pericles, ii. 12, § 4. Perioeci (in Argos), v. 3, § 7 : — (in Crete), ii. 9, §3; 10, §§ 3, 5, 8, 16 : — advantageous to have perioeci of foreign race as cul- tivators, vii. 9, § 8 ; 10, § 13. Perrhaebians, the, ii. 9, § 3. Persia, iii. 13, § 19; v. 10, §§8, 24; II, §§4, 6; vii. 2, § 10 ; viii. 5, § 5. Persian War, the : see War, Persian. Perversions, the, of the true forms of government, iii. i,§§8-io; 6, § 11; 7 ; 17, § I ; iv. 2, §§ 1-3 ; 8, § I ; all governments perversions of the perfect state, iv. 8, § I (cp. ii. II, § 5). Phalaris, of Agrigentum, v. 10, §6. Phaleas of Chalcedon, ii. 7, § 2 ; 12, §§ 7, 12. Pharsalus, v. 6, § 10. Pheidon, tyrant of Argos, v. 10, §6. Pheidon, of Corinth, ii. 6, § 13. Philip, King of Macedonia, v. 10, § 16. Philolaus, ii. 12, §§ 8, 10. Philosopher, the, may be allowed to discuss practical questions, i. II, §1; has no difficulty in acquiring wealth, ib. §§8-io; must go below the surface of things, iii. 8, § i ; his life as distinguished from that of the statesman, vii. 2, §6: — philo- sophers, the, not agreed about slavery, i. 6, § 2 ; the opinions of natural philosophers about marriage, vii. 16, § 11 ; philo- sophers who have treated of musical education, viii. 5, § 23; 7, §§2, 3,8,11,14. Philosophy, especially necessary in the prosperous, vii. 15, §§3, 4- Philoxenus, viii. 7; §§ lOj H- Phocis, V. 4, § 7, Phocylides, quoted, iv. 11, § 9. Phoxus, tyrant of Chalcis, v. 4, §9. Phreatto, court of, at Athens, iv. 16, §3- Phrygian harmony, the : see Har- mon)'. Phrynichus, v. 6, § 6. Phylarchs, magistrates at Epi- damnus, v. i, § 10. Physician, the, must be jiadged by the physician, iii. 11, §§ 10-12 ; is healed by the physician, ib. ]6, § 8 ; is not expected to per- suade or coerce his patients, vii. 2, § 13 ; must know both the end and the means of his art, ib. 13, § 2 ; precepts of the physicians about marriage, ib. 16, § II ; law about physicians in Egypt, iii. 15, § 4. Piraeus, ii. 8, § i ; v. 3, § 15. Pittacus, ii. 12, §13; iii. 14, §§ 9, lo- Plato, criticisms of; — forms of government differ in kind, i. i , § 2 ; 3. § 4 ; 7> § I ; the virtue of men and women not the same, i' I3> §§9-11 ) slaves not al- ways to be harshly treated, ib. § 14 ; disadvantages of com- munity of wives and children, ii. I. § 3-c. 5 ; of common pro- perty, ib. 5; vii. 10, §9; the unity of the state may be carried too far, ii. 2, § 2-c. 3, §4:4, §6; 5, §13; men and women ought not to have the 344 Index same pursuits, ib. 5, § 24 ; dan- ger from the rulers being always the same, ib. §§25, 26; hap- piness should not be confined to one class, ib. § 27 ; Plato has neglected the foreign rela- tions of his state, ib. 6, § 7 ; amount of property allowed by him insufficient, ib. § 9 ; he should have limited population as well as property, ib. §§ 10- 14; 7, §4; he has not said how the rulers and subjects are related, ib. 0, § 14; why should not property in land be increased to a certain extent? ib. §15 ; diffi- culty of living in two houses, ib. §16; the best state not made up of tyranny and demo- cracy, ib. § 18 ; the state of the Laws really a mixture. of oligarchy and democracy, ib. §§ 18-22 ; Plato's distinctions between good and bad constitu- tions, iv. 2, § 3 ; his account of the classes necessary to a state, ib. 4, §§ 12-15 ; has not recog- nized the 'Polity' in his enu- meration of constitutions, ib. 7, § I ; his theory of revolutions, V. 12, §§7-18; his error in saying that the guardians should be fierce to those whom they do not know, vii. 7, §§5-8 :— that a valiant city needs no walls, ib. II, § 8 : — that the crying of children should be checked, ib. 17, §6; his inconsistency in retaining the Phrygian mode, viii. 7, §§ 8-13 : — the merits of Plato's writings, ii. 6, § 6 ; he departs from ordinary practice more than other legislatois, ib. 7, § I ; peculiarities suggested by him, ib. 12, § i -' : — ^justice of his censure of the Lacedae- monian constitution, ib. 9, § 34: — how far right in wishing that his city should not be near the sea, vii. 6, §§1-4 : — speech of Aristophanes in the Symposium quoted, ii. 4, § 6 : — criticism of the Republic, ib. i, §3-0. 5; of the Laws, ib. 6. Pleasure, always sought by man- kind, i. 9, § 16; ii. 7, § 12 ; denied byPlatotohisguardians, ii, 5, 9 27; is regarded difi'cr- ently by different persons, viii. 3, §5; the pleasure of living, iii. 6, §4; relation of pleasure to happiness, vii. i,§6; liienatural pleasure given by music, viii. 5, §§ II, 15, 17, 25; 6, § 8:— Pleasures, the, which are unac- companied by pain, ii. 7, § 12. Poetry, better judged by the many than the individual, iii. 11, § 3. Polity : j^f Government, the Con- stitutional. Polycrates, v. 11, § 9. Polygnolus, the painter, viii. 5, § 21. Poor, the, everywhere abound, iii. 8, § 6 ; v. i, § 14 ; covet the goods of the rich, iv. 11, § 9 ; tlieir degiaded state in Hellenic cities, ib. §§5-7; willing to fight if they are su[)- portecl by the state, ib. 13, S 9; equal to the rich in democracies, vi. 2, § 9 ; the surplus revenue distributed among thc-m in the extreme democracy, ib. 5, § 7 ; may cause a revolution if their niimbeis increase, v. 3, §§ 6-S ; begrudge the extravagance of courts, ib. 11, § 19 ; should be humanely treated, ii. 7, §20; iv. 13, §8; should be helped by the rich, vi. 5, §§ 5-1 1. Population, decline of, at Sparta, ii. 9. § 16; importance of regu- lating, ib. 6, §§ 10-14; 7, §§'4- Index 345" 6; 9, §§14-19; vii. 5, § i ; 16, §15; changes of government brought about by the natural increase of population in Hellas, iii. 15, § 13; iv. 6, § 5; 13, § 10 ; m. 5, § 5 ; a limit of population necessary to good government, ii. 6, §§6, 10; 7, § 5; 9> § 19; '^'"- 4. §§4-" ; 5, §i; 16, § 15. Poverty, not the cause of the worst crimes, ii. 7, § 10 ; always antagonistic to riches, iv. 4, § 19 ; the parent of revolution and crime, ii. 6, § 13 {but cp. v. 12, §17); one of the essential characteristics of democracy, vi. 2, §7- Priests, are not political officers, iv. 15, § 2 ; necessary to the state, vii. 8, §§ 7, 9; should be taken from the aged citizens who are past state service, ib. 9, §9; their duties, vi. 8, §§ 18- 20 ; required to take their meals at common tables, vii. 12, § 6. Property, a part of the household, i. 4, § I ; 8, § I ; a condition but not a part of the state, vii. 8, §4; in the sense of food, provided by nature for all, i. 8, § 9 ; 10, § 3 ; — the pleasure of property, ii. 5, § 8 ;— Plato's limit of property unsatisfactory, ib. 6, § 9 ; the limit should be such as to enable a man to live both temperately and liberally, ib. ; vii. 5, § i ; — inequality of property at Sparta, ii. 9, §§ 14- 19; V- 7. § 3. 10; 12, § 15;— a great cause of revolutions, ii. 7, §§2-6. Property, community of ; criti- cism of Plato's scheme, ii. 5 (^see Plato) ; common property opposed to human nature, ib. §§4, 16; exists in a moGilied degree among friends, ib. §§6, 7 ; vii. 10, § 9 ; found to some extent at Sparta andTarentum, ii- .=^> §7; vi* .5) §16; would destroy the virtues of temper- ance and liberality, ii. 5, §§ 8- 10 ; would not produce the marvellous results which Plato expects, ib. § 11 ; — equalization of, proposed by Phaleas, ib. 7 ; 12, § 12 ; would not remedy the deeper evils of human nature, ib. 7, §§S-i.^, 18. Property qualification, required in the holders of various offices, iii. II, § 16; iv. 4, § 24; 5, § I ; 6, §§ 3, 7 ; vi. 4, § 5 ; ought not to be excessive, iv. 13, § 7 ; in oligarchies should be fixed according to two stan- dards, vi. 6, § 2 ; changes in, a cause of revolutions, v. 3, §§ 8, 10: 6, §§ 16-18; 7, §9; the evil may be remedied by pe- riodical revisions of the census, ib. 8, §§ 10, II. Proportion, importance of, iii. 13, § 21 ; iv. 12 ; V. i, §§ 12- 15; 3. §6; 7, §8; 8,§i2; 9, § 7 ; vii. 4, § 10. Psammetichus, son of Gordius, tyrant at Corinth, v. 12, § 3. Pyramids, the, of Egypt, v. 11, §9- Reason, an element of virtue, vii. 13, §§ 10-13; 15, § 7; is the master artificer, i. 13, § 8; di- vided into two parts, the specu- lative and the practical, vii. 14, § 10 ; is the end towards which nature strives, ib. 15, §8; in- tended by nature to control the passionate or irrational element in the soul, i. 5, § 6 ; 13, § 6 ; vii. 14, § 9 ; 15, § 8 ; is not found in the animals, i, 2, § 11; 34<^ Index vii. 13, § 12 ; exists in slaves to alimitedcxtent, i.5,§ 9; 13, §3; is not readily obeyed by those vvlio have great advantages over others, iv. 11, §5; may be overcome by passion, v. 10, § 33 ; 1 1 , § 31 ; may make mis- takes, vii. 15, § 7. Religion, matters of, used to be entrusted to the kings, iii. 14, §§ 3, 14 (cp. vi. 8, § 20) ; the tyrant should have a care of religion, v. 11, §25; the ex- pense of public worship should be borne by the state, vii. 10, § 10: — the officers of religion, vi. 8, §§ 18-21 ; vii. 8, § 9 ; 9, §9- Religious worship, one of the conditions of the state, vii. 8, §8. Representation, principle of, once existed in the government of Mantinea, vi. 4, § 4. Republic, the, of Plato : see Plato. Rest : see Leisure. Retail trade, not a natural mode of money-making, i. 9, §§ 4, 12 ; arises out of the barter of necessary articles, ib. §§ 9-12. Revolutions, their objects, v. i ; their causes, ii. 7, §§ 2, 5, 10; v. 2; 3; 4; 10, § 13; 12, §§14-18; their occasions, v. 4 ; 7> § 1 1 » the preventives of them, ii. 11, § 15 ; v. 7, § 6 ; 8 ; 9 ; 1 1 ; vi. 4, §§ 16-20 ; 5 ; 6 ; revolutions in democracies, v. 5 ; — in oligarchies, ib. 6 ; — in constitutional governments, ib. § 1 7 ; 7, § 5 ; — in aristocracies, ib. 7; — in monarchies, ib. 10; — in tyrannies, ib. ; 11; Plato's theory of revolutions, criticized, ib. 12, §§ 7-18; — questions raised after revolutitns: citizens dejure and de facto, iii. 2, §§34 5 ; should old debts be paid- ib. 3, § I ;— democratic mea- sures taken by Cleisthenes and others after a revolution, ib. 2, §§ 3-,S ; vi. 4, § 18 ; revolutions may happen without an imme- diate change in the constitution, iv. .s,§3; V. I, §8. Rhcgium, ii. 12, § 14; v. 12, § I.'.. Rhodes, ii. 10, § 3 ; v. 3, §§ 4, 5 ; 5> § 2. Rich, the, one of the elements of the state, iv. 4, §15; every- where few compared to the poor, iii. 8, §6; v. i, §14; often hindered bythecares of property from attending to public busi- ness, iv. 6, § 6 ( but cp. i. 7, § 5) ; possess the external advantages of which the want occasions crime, iv. 8, §4 (cp. ii. 7, § 10); have toomucli pov^'er in so-called aristocratical governments, iv. 12, §6; v. 7, §7; their en- croachments more dangerous to the state than those of the poor, iv. I 2, §6 ; constantly in antago- nism to the poor, ib. 11, §7; v. 9, § 10 ; should be protected against the demagogues, v. 8, § 20 ; vi. 5, § 3 ; should be relieved from useless state cx- ])cnses, V. 8, § 20 ; vi. 5, § 9 ; should be generous to the poor, iv. 13, § 8 ; vi. 5, § 10 ; should be public-spirited and munifi- cent, vi. 7, § 6 ; are often spoilt by indulgence in childhood, iv. ii,§6;v. 9, §13; can alone afford the expense of keeping horses, iv. 3, § 2. Riches and poverty, the opposing elements of the slate, v. i, §14; 8, § 14; riches more de- sired by men than honour, iv. Index 3 47 I3> §S ; V. 8, § i6; vi. 4, § 2; Solon wrong in thinking that ' no bound has been fixed to riches,' i. 8, § 14. See Wealth. Koyalty, the form of government in which one rules for the best, iii. 7, § 3 ; V. 10, § 3; analogous to aristocracy, v. 10, §§2, 7; opposed to tyranny, iii. 7, §5 ; iv. 2, § 2 ; V. 10, § 2 ; is it better than the rule of the law? iii. 15 ; 16; arose (i) from the government of families by the eldest,!. 2, § C ; 7, § i ; 12, §3; (2) from services rendered by the first chiefs, iii. 14, § 12 ; i5,§ii; V. 10, §§ 3, 8 ; (3) from the weakness of the middle and lower classes, iv. 1 3 , § 1 1 ; once existed in Crete, ii. 10, § 6 ; has various forms : (i) the Lacedae- monian (which is only a general- ship for life), ii. 9, § 33 ; "i- 14, §§3. 14; i5> §§ I, 2; 16, §1; (2) the despotic (among Bar- barians), iii. 14, §§6, 14; iv. 10, § 2 ; (3) the ancient Dicta- torships, iii. 14, §§8, 14 ; iv. 10, § 2 ; (4) the monarchies of the heroic age, iii. 14, §§ 11-14; (5) the absolute monarchy, ib. § 15 ; — the people to whom royalty is suited, ib. c. 17; — causes of revolutions in mon- archies, V. 10 ; means of their preservation, ib. 11, §§1-3; royalty more often destroyed from within than from without, ib. 10, § 36 ; true royalty un- known in later Hellas, ib. § 37; vii. 14, § 3. ^i?i?King, Monarchy. Rule ; the various kinds of rule essentially different from each other, i. I, § 2 ; 3, § 4 ; 5, § 6; 7, § I ; 12; 13, §§4-8; iii. 6, §§5-7; vii. 3, §2 ; 14, §6; the distinction between the ruler and the ruled foimd throughout nature, i. 2, § 2 ; 5, §§ 2-7 ; the better the ruled, the better the rule, ib. 5, §§ 2, 7 j V. 1 1, § 34 ; the rule of free- men better than despotic au- thority, vii. 14, § 19 ; rule over ethers, not the highest object of the legislator, ib. 14, §§ 14-22; rule must be learnt by obedience, iii. 4, S§ 10, 14; vii. 9, §6; 14. § 6. Ruler, the, ought to have moral virtue in perfection, i. 13, § 8 ; the virtue peculiar to him, iii. 4, § 17 ; must learn to govern by obedience, ii. 11, § 14 ; iii. 4, § 14; vii. 9, § 6 ; 14, § 6; the rulers ought to remain the same, ii. 2, §§4-8; vii. 14, § 2 ; dangers arising from this arrangement, ii. 5, §§ 24-27 ; vii. 14, §3; the difficiilty solved, if the elder rule, and the younger obey, vii. 9, § 5; 14, § 5. Salamis, victory of, v. 4, § 8. Samos, iii. 13, § 19 ; v. 3, § 12 ; II, § 9- Sardanapalus, v. 10, § 22. Science, the, of the statesman, L I, § 2; 10, § I ; iii. 12, § I ; iv. I, § 3; — ofthe master, i. 3, § 4 ; 7, §§ 2, 4;— of the slave, ib. 7, §§2, 3 ; in all sciences the whole must be resolved into the parts, ib. i, § 3 ; every science capable of improvement, ii. 8, §18; the philosophical student of science must not neglect any detail, iii. 8, § i ; all sciences aim at some good, ib. 12, § i ; — the political science the highest of all sciences, iii. 12, § i; aims at the good of the state, vii. 2, § 4 ; the subjects which it in- cludes, iv. I, §§3-11. 348 Index Scylax, vii. 14, § 3. Scylletic Gulf, the, vii. 10, § 3. Scythians, the, vii. 2, 5§ 10, 11. Sedition : see Revolution. Self-sufficiency, the, of the state, the end and the best, i. 2, § S ; vii. 5, § I ; S, § S ; w^ould not be promoted by extreme unifi- cation, ii. 2, § 8. Senate : see Council of Elders. Senators: .y^^ Councillor?. Servant, the, a kind of instrument in the arts, i. 4, § 2 ; many ser- vants often less efficient than a few, ii. 3, § 4 ; tlie servants who are employed in daily life, those with whom we most often disagree, ib. 5, § 4 ; children not to be left too much to ser- vants, vii. 17, § 7. See Slave. Sesostris, king of Egypt, vii. 10, §§i,6. Seuthes, v. 10, § 24. Shepherds, lead the laziest life among men, i. 8, §6; some- times combine brigandage with their other occupations, ib. § 8 ; form the second best material of a democracy, vi. 4, §§ i, 11 ; make excellent soldiers, ib. § il. Sicily, ii. 10, § 4 ; v. 12, § 13. Sicyon, v. 12, § i. Simos (?), a party leader at Larissa, v. 6, § 13. Sirrhas, v. 10, § 17. Slave, the, does he exist by nature? i. 4, § 6-c. 6 ; different from tiie I'emale (except among I'arba- rians), ib. 2, §§ 2-4 ; how re- lated to his master, ib. §§ 2-5 ; 3, §§1-3; 4, §5; vii. 3, §5; not always distinguished by nature from the freeman, i. 5, § 10 ; 6, § 8 ; the relation be- tween slave and master, when natural, does not exclude kind- ness, ib. 6, § 9 ; slave and master have a common interest, ib. 2, § 3 ; iii. 6, § 6 ; the slave must not be addressed in the language of command only [against Plato, Laws, vi. 777], i. 13, § 14; place oftheslavtr in the management of the family, ib. 4 ; 5, § 9 ; 8, § I ; the slave an instrument taking precedence of other instruments, ib. 4, § 2 ; like the animals, ministers to the needs of life, ib. 5, § 9 ; the science proper to him, i. 7, §§2,3; his share in virtue, in, 13, §§ 2-14 ; — in reason, ib. 5, §§ S, 9; 13- §3 ; has not the deliberative faculty, ib. 13, § 7> is nearer to his master than tlie mechanic, ib. § 13 ; ought to be trained in virtue by him, ib. § 14 : — Slaves, how related to artisans, i. 1 3, § 1 3 ; ii- 7, § 2 2 ; iii. 4, § 12; 5, § 3 ; forbidden gymnastic exercises in Crete, ii. 5, § 19 ; difficulty in managing them, ib. § 22 : 9, §§ 2-4; vii. ! o, §13; the different classes of slaves, iii. 4, § 12 ; children of slaves only admitted to citizen- ship in extreme democracies, ib. 5, § 7 ; vi. 4, § 16; slaves can- not form a stale, iii. 9, § 6; can- not be self-sufficient, iv. 4, § 11; licence allowed to them in democracies and tyrannies, v. II, § II ; vi. 4, § 20 ; some- times emancipated by tyrants to serve as a guard, v. 11, §32; should be encouraged by the hojie of freedom, vii. 10, § 14; their company dangerous for children, ib. 17, § 7. Slavery, is it according to nature ? i. 5 ; 6. Slavery ; — men should not think it slavery to live according to the constitution, v. 9, § 15. Index 349 Slaves, the art of acquiring, a species of hunting or war, i. 7j §5 ; vii. 14, § 21. Smerdis, v. 10, § 19. Society, political, the highest of allcommunities,i. I, § 1 ; exists, not for mere companionship, but for the sake of noble actions, iii. 9, §§ 12-14; man designed by nature to take part in society, i. 2, §§ 8-16 ; iii. 6, § 3 ; bene- fit conferred on manliind by the establishment of society, i. 2, § 15 ; society cannot exist with- out judicial deci -lions and punish- ments, vi. 8, § 9 ; vii. 13, § 6. Socrates : see Plato. Soldiers, according to Plato, should be taught to use both hands alike, ii. 12, § 12 ; shep- herds make excellent soldiers, vi. 4, § II ; relation of the dif- ferent kinds of soldiers to the different constitutions, ib. 7, §§ 1-3 i the soldier must have a good knowledge of the mili- tary art, vii. II, § 12 ; soldiers as necessary to the state as artisans or husbandmen [against Plato, Rep. ii. 369], iv. 4, §§ 10- 17; vii. 4, §§4-7; 8, § 7; 9, § 10 ; the soldiers should be taken from the youth, the coun- cillors from the old, vii. 9, §§ 3-10 ; 14, § 5 ; should form a separate caste, as in Egypt, ib. 9, § 10 ; ID, § I ; position of the soldiers in the constitution of Hippodamus, ii. 8, §§ 2, 8- 12. Soldiers, heavy-armed , citizenship in constitutional governments confined to the, ii. 6, § 16 ; iii. 7, §4; 17, § 4; iv. 13, § 10; growth of their iniportance in Hellenic slates, iv. 13, §§9-12 ; taken from the roll of c.tizens at Athens, v. 3, §7; form (with cavalry) the natural military force of an oligarchy, vi. 7, §§ 1,2 ; generally worsted by the light-armed in popular insurrec- tions, ib. § 3 ; — the principal magistrates elected from those who are serving, or who have served, ii. 8, § 9 ; iv. 13, § 9. Soldiers, light-armed, always at- tached to democracy, vi. 7, § 2; generally master the heavy- armed in popular insurrections, ib. § 3 ; the younger citizens in oligarchies should be trained in the exercises of light infantry, ib. Solon, i. 8, § 14 ; ii. 7, § 6 ; 12, §§ 2-6 (cp. iii. II, § 8) ; iv. 11, §15- Sophocles, quoted, i. 13, § 11. Soul, the, rules by nature over the body, i. 5, §§ 4-6 ; poste- rior to the body in order of generation, vii. 15, §9; more truly a part of an animal than the body, iv. 4, § 14 ; the beauty of the soul less easily seen than that of the body, i. 5, § 11 ; the interests of soul and body the same, ib. 6, §10; the ir- rational element in the soul subject to the rational, ib. 5, §6; 13, §6; vii. 14, §9 ; 15, § 8 ; the divisions of the soul, i- 5, §§5-7; 13, §6; iii. 4> § 6 ; vii. 14, § 9 ; 15, § 9 ; the soul never wholly free from passion, iii. 15, § 5 ; said to be or to possess harmony, viii. 5, § 25. Sparta : see Lacedaemon. Speculation, life of, opposed to that of contemplation, vii. 2 ; 3; 14. §§9-22. State, the, is the highest of com- munities, i. I, § I ; is based upon 3fo Index the relations ofhusband and wife, father and child, master and slave, ruler and subject, ib. 2 ; 13, § 15 ; formed of a union of villages, ib. 2, §8 ; exists for the sake of a good life, ib. ; iii. p, §§ 6-14; iv. 4, §11; vii. I, §1; 8, §§4, 8;— not for the sake of alliance and security, iii. 9, §§6-14; is distinguished from an alliance because it has an ethical aim, ii. 2, § 3 ; iii. 9, § 8 ; — from a nation, because it is made up of different elements, ii. 2, § 3 ; is not necessarily formed by a number of persons residing together, iii. 3, § 3 ; 9, §§9-12 ; (Jiiit cp. ii. I, § a) ; is a work of nature, i. 2, §§ 8, 9 ; prior to the family or the individual, ib. § 12; 13, § 15 : — composed of dissimilar parts or elements, ii. 2, § 3 ; iii. i, § 2 ; 4, §§ 6-8 ; iv. 3, § I ; 4, § 7 ; 12, §§1-4; V. I, §§ 12-15; 3» § 6 ; vii. 8 ; the parts not to be identified with the conditions of the state, vii. 8, § i ; the parts and conditions enumerated, iv. 3, §§i-6; 4, §§7-20; vii. 8, § 7 ; — compared to the parts of animals, iv. 4, §§ 7-9 : — thestate depends for its identity mainly on the sameness of the constitu- tion, iii. 3 ; must be able to de- fend itself, ii. 6, § 7 ; 7, §§ 14- 17; 10, § 15; iii- 12, § 9; iv. 4, § 10; vii. 4, §6; 15, §2; should be self-sufficing, i. 2, §8 ; ii. 2,§ 8 ; vii. 4, §11 ; 5, § i ; 8, § 8 ; sliould not exceed a certain size, ii. 6, §6; iii. 3, §§4-7; vii. 4; 5, § I ; — has the same virtue, and therefore the same life and end, as the individual, vii. 1-3 ; 13-15 ; may, like an individual, be wanting in self-discipline, v. 9, § 12 ; must have the virtues of leisure, vii. 15, § i ; can lead a life of virtuous activity isolated from others, ib. 2, § 16 ; 3, §§S- 10 ; is not made happier by conquest, ib. 2 ; 3; 14, §§ I4- 22 ; rests upon justice, i. 2, § 16; vii. 14, § 3 ; must have a care of virtue, iii. 9, § 8 ; vii. 13, § 9 (cp. iv. 7, § 4) ; must be happy, not in regard to a portion of the citizens, but to them all, ii. 5, §27; vii. 9, §7 ; is imited by friendship among the citizens, ii. 5, §6; iii. 9, § 13; iv. 11, §7; V. II, §5 (cp.vi. 5, §7); must pay great regard to edu- cation, i. 13, § 15; ii. 7, § 8; v. 9, § 1 1 ; viii. i : — must not be left to fortune, ii. 11, §§ 15, 16; vii. 13, § 9; is not the growth of a day, v. 3, § ii ; is preserved by the principle of compensation, ii. 2, §§ 4-7; is sometimes left at the mercy of the army by the violence of faction, v. 6, § 13 ; its perma- nence can only be secured by the toleration of all elements, ii. 9, § 22 ; iv. 9, § 10; 12, § i; V. 8, § 5 ; 9. § 5 ; vi. 6, § 2 ; any state, however ill-constituted, may last a few days, vi. 5, § i : — the various claims to autho- rity in the state, iii. 9, §§ 1-5, 14; 10; 12; 13; iv. 8, §9; vi. 3, §§1-4; what share in the state may be allowed to the ordinary citizen? iii. 11, §§6- 8; iv. 13, §§5-8; vi. 4, §5; 7, § 5 (cp. ii. 12, §5). State, the ideal, of Aristotle, would require (i) a defensible position, vii. 5, § 3; (2) a mode- rate naval force, ib. §§ 6-9; (3) courageous and intelligent citizens, ib. 7 ; (4) the exclusion Index 3fi of ireclinnics and tradesmen from citizenship, ib. 9, § § i-S ; (5) slaves and Perioeci to till the soil, ib. §8; 10, §§9, 13, 14 ; (6) common meals, ib. lo, §§ 1-8, 10; (7) subdivision of the land into two parts, public and private, ib. §ii; (8) [for the city^ a central situation, ib. 5> § 3 ; 1 1 ) § 2 ; — near, but not upon, the sea, ib. 6, §§ 1-6; a healthy site, ib. 11, § i ; a good water supply, ib. § 3 ; proper fortifications and walls, ib. §§5, 8-1 2 ; an arrangement of houses and streets which will combine the advantages of beauty and security, ib. § 6 ; an acropolis, for the temples, and a ' freemen's agora,' ib. 12, §§i-6; govern- ment buildings and a trader's agora, ib. 7. State, the best [absolutely], the enquirer into, must examine the best ideal and actual forms of government, ii. i, § i;differsfrom the so-called aristocracies be- cause the citizens are absolutely good, iii. 13, § 12 ; iv. 7, § 2 (3«^cp. iii. 4, §5); presupposes the best life, vii. i ; in compari- son with it, all existing govern- ments maybe called perversions, iv. 8, § I. State, the best [under ordinary circumstances] , iv. i ,§ 3; 1 1 , § 2 1 (cp. ii. 6, § 16}. State, the best [for mankind in general], iv. i, § 3 ; 11, §1. Statesman, the, is properly con- cerned with the natural art of acquisition only, i. 8, § 15; 10, § I ; ought also to be acquainted with the art of money-making, ib. n,§i3; must be able tore- cognize evils at their commence- ment, V. 4, §3; 8, §9; must not despise small things, ib. 3, §10; 4, §1; 7, §11; 8, §2; must he have virtue, or is skill alone sufficient ? ib. 9, §§1-4; must know the real effect of political measures, ib. § 9 ; will use fear as a means to bind the state together, ib. 8, § 8 ; will not suppose that the great- ness of the state depends merely on size, vii. 4, § 4; the life of the statesman contrasted with the life of the philosopher, ib. 2, § 6. Statesman, the, the rule of, dif- ferent from other kinds of rule, i. I, §2; 3, §4; 7, §1, Stentor, vii. 4, § 11. Sybaris, v. 3, §§ 11, 12. Symposium, the, of Plato : see Plato, Syracuse, i. 7, § 2 ; iii. 15, § 16; V. 3. §§6> 13; 4, §§1-4.9; 5. § 10; 6, § 8; 10, §§6, 23, 28, 30-2; II, §§ 7, 10; 12, §§6, 12. Syrtis (?), a district of Southern Italy, vii. 10, § 5. Tarentum, iv. 4, § 21 ; v. 3, § 7 ; 7, § 2 ; vi. 5, § 10. Telecles, of Miletus, iv. 14, § 4. Tenedos, iv. 4, § 21. Thales, of Miletus, i. 11, § 8 :— [probably the Cretan poet], ii. 12, §7- Theagenes, tyrant of Megara, v. 5, §9- Thebes; ii. 9, §§ 10, 16; 12, §10; iii. 5: §7; V. 3, §5; 6, §15; vi. 7, §4. I'heodectes, quoted, i. 6, § 7. Theodorus, the actor, vii. 17, §13- Theopompus, king of Sparta, v. II, § 2. Thera, one of the Sporades, iv. 4>§5- m Index Thessaly, ii. 5, § 22 ; 9, § 2 ; vii. 12, § 3. Thetcs, the (in Solon's constitu- tion), ii. 12, § 6. Thibron, vii. 14, § 17. Thirty, the, government of, at Athens, v. 6, § 6. Thracians, the, vii. 2, § 10. Thras}bulus (brother of Hiero), V. 10, § ,^i ; 12, § 6. Thrasybulus, tyrant of Miletus, in. 13, § 16 ; V. 10, § 13. Thrasyllus, viii. 6, § 12. Thrasymachus, v. 5, § 4. Thurii, V. 3, §§ 11," 12; 7, §§ 9, 12. Timophanes of Corinth, v. 6, § 12. Timophanes, of Mitylene, v. 4, §6. Trade : see Commerce. Traders, the employments of, de- void of moral excellence, vi. 4, §12; vii. 9, § 3 ; ought to be excluded from citizensb.ip, vii. 9, § 3 ; admitted to olTice at Thebes after they had retired from business ten years, iii. 5, § 7 ; vi. 7, § 4. Triopium, promontory near Cnidus, ii. 10, § 3. Troezen, v. 3, § 11 ; vii. 16, § 7, Tyrannicide, esteemed honour- able in Flellas, v. 10, § 26. Tyranny, the government of the monarch who rules for his own interests, iii. 7, § 5 ; 8, § 2 ; iv. lo» § ,S i V. 10, §9; akin to democracy, iv. 4, § 27 ; v. 10, § § 1 1 , 30 ; 1 1 , § I 2 ; hardly to be called a constitution, iv. 8, § I ; ID, § I ; tlie perversion of royalty, iii. 7, § 5 ; 17> § ' ; iv- 2, § 2 ; 4, §27; 5, § 2; 10, § 3 ; does not rest upon natural justice or expediency, iii. 17, § I ; has all the vices both of democracy and olij^archy, v. 10, §§ II, 30, 35 ; is unendur- able to freemen, iv. 10, § 4 ; v. 11, § 13 ; may arise either from extreme oligarchy ordemocracy, iv. II, §11; V. S,§7; in Sicily, often arose out of oligarchy, v. 12, §13; viras common in an- cient times, owing to the great powers of the magistrates, ib. 5, § 8 ; 10, § 5 ; always a short- lived government, ib. 12, §1; rarely becomes hereditary, ib. 10, § 33 ; causes of revolution in tyrannies, ib. 10 ; means of their preservation, ib. ii ; governments into which tyranny may change, ib. 12, § 11. Tyrant, the, is the natural enemy of the freeman, iv. 10, §4; v. 11, § 13 ; cuts off his rivals, iii. 13, §§ 16-19; V. 10, §13 ; II, § 5 ; rules over involuntary sub- jects as the king over voluntary, iii. 14, § 7 ; aims at pleasure, the king at honour, v. 10, § 10; is guarded by mercenaries, iii. 14, § 7 ; V, 10, § 10 ; sometimes obliged to emancipate the slaves, V. II, § 32 ; is much under the influence of flatterers, iv. 4, § 2S; V. II, § 12 ; destroys the spirit and confidence of his subjects, V. II, §§4, 13, 15; sends spies among them, ib. § 7 ; incites ihem to quarrel, ib. § 8 ; oppresses them by war and taxa- .tion, ib. ; distrusts his friends, ib. § 10 ; gives licence to slaves and women, ib. § 1 1 ; vi. 4, § 20 ; loves the bad, v. 11, § 12 ; pre- fers foreigners to citizens, ib. § 14; is capable of any wicked- ness, ib. ; is full of self-indul- gence and sensuality, ib. §23; may also preserve his tyranny by playing the ' father of his Index 3f3 country,' ib. §§ 17-33; must be on his guard against assassins, especially against those who think that they have been in- sulted, ib. § 30 ; must conciliate the poor or the rich, whichever is the stronger, ib. § 32. Tyrants, the, of Hellenic cities put down by the Lacedae- monians, iii. 2, § 3 ; V. ID, § 30 ; of Sicily, by the Syracusans, v. 10, §30. Tyrants, most of the ancient, originally demagogues, v. 5, §6; 10, §4; sometimes great magistrates, or kings, ib. 5, §8 ; 10, § 5. Tyrrhenians, the, iii. 9, § 6. Tyrtaeus, v. 7, § 4. Usury, the most unnatural mode of money-making, i. 10, §5; 11. §3- Utility, too much regarded by Hellenic legislators, vii. 14, §15; is not the sole aim of education, viii. 2, §3; 3, §11; is not sought after by men of noble mind, ib. 3, § 12. Village, the, acolonyofthe family, i. 2, §6; the state a union ot villages, ib. § 8. Virtue, the especial characteristic of aristocratical governments, ii. II, §§ 5-10; iv. 7; V. 7, §§ 5- 7 ; often allied to force, i. 6, § 3 ; more a concern of household management than wealth, ib. 1 3, § I ; depends upon the supre- macy of the rational principle in the soul, ib. §6; vii. 14, §9; 15, §9; cannot be included under a general definition, i. 13, § 10 ; must be taught to the slave by his master, ib. §12; ought to be the aim and care of the state, iii. 9, §§6-S; vii. i.^, §9 (cp- iv. 7, §4); gives a claim to superiority in the state, iii. 9, §§ 14, 15; 13, §1; has many kinds, ib. 7, § 4; cannot ruin those who possess her, ib. 10, § 2 ; is a mean, iv. 11, § 3 ; how far required in the great officers of state, v. 9, §§ 1-4; must be at least pretended by the tyrant, ib. 11, §§ 25, 34; is regarded as a secondary object by mankind, vii. i, §5: — can- not be separated from happiness, vii, I, § 3 ; 2, § 2 ; 3, § I ; 8, § 5; 9' § 3; 13. § 5; results from nature, habit, and reason, ib. 13, §§ 10-13 ; i.S. §§7-io; is not a matter of chance, ib. 13, § 9 ; how far consistent with the political life, ib. 2:3; should it be made the aim of education? viii. 2; consists in hating and lov- ing and rejoicing aright, ib. 5, § 17 : — should not (as is done by the Lacedaemonians) be sup- posed inferior to external goods, ii. 9,§35 (cp. vii. I, §5); nor be practised with a view to the single object of success in war, ii- 9' § 34; vii. 2,§ 9; 14, § 16; 15, §6: — the virtue proper to the slave, the woman, the child, i. 13, §§ 1-3; of the ruler and the subject different, ib. §§ 4-6; iii. 4, §§ 7-1 8; of the ruler, practical wisdom, of the subject, true opinion, iii. 4, § 18 ; of men and women not the same, i. 13, §§3, 9-11; iii. 4, §16; less required in the artisan than the slave, i. 13, § 12 (cp. vii. 9, §7); of the citizen relative to the constitution, iii. 4, §§ 1-7 ; iv. 7, § 3 ; V. 9, § I ; of the good man absolute, iii. 4, §§ 1-7 ; vii. 13, §7; ofthe good citizen: 3/4 Index — is it identical with that of the good man V iii. 4 ; 5, § 10 ; 18; vii. 14, §8; of the citizen in the perfect state, iii. 4, § 5 ; J3. § 12; iv. 7, § 2. Virtue, military, is found in the masses, iii. 7, § 4 ; the social, is justice, i. 2, § 16; iii. 13, §3. Virtues, the, of women and child- ren important to the state, i. 13. § i.S ) i'- 9> § 5 ; of the state and the individual the same, vii. I, § 12; of the military life, "• 9. §§ "> 34; vii. 15, §3; of leisure, vii. 15, § i. War, a part of the art of acqui- sition when directed against wild beasts and against men who are intended by nature to be slaves, i. 7, § 5 ; 8, §12; vii. 2, § 15 ; 14, § 21 ; exists forthe sake of peace, vii. 14, §§ 13, 22 ; 15, § I ; a school of virtue, ii. 9, § 1 1 ; a remedy against the dangers of prosperity, vii. 15, § 3 ; constant war a part of tyrannical policy, v. 11, § 10 ; success in war the sole object of the Lacedaemonian and Cretan constitutions, ii. 9, §§ 34, 35 ; vii. 2, §9; 14, § 16; 15, §6; progress in war : — invention of tactics, iv. 13, §10; — of siege machines, vii. 11, § 9 ; improve- ment of fortifications, ib. § 12. War, captives taken in, ought they to be made slaves? i. 6, §§i-8. War, the Peloponnesian ; losses of the Athenian nobihty, v. 3, § 7 ; battle of Oenophyta, ib. §5; — capture of Mitylene, ib. 4, § 6 ; — battle of Mantinea, ib. §9; — the Sicilian expedition, ib. ; — the Four Hundred at Athens, ib. § 13 ; 6, § 6 ;— the Thirty, ib. 6, §6. War, the Persian, v. 3, § 7 ; 4, §§ 4, 8 ; 7, § 4 ; effect of, upon Athens, ii. 12, § 5 ; v. 4, § 8 ; viii. 6, § II : — the Sacred, v. 4, §7. \\ ealth, always antagonistic to poverty, iv. 4, § 19; forms an element of the state, ii. 7, § 16 ; iv. 4, § 15; vii. 8, §§ 7, 9; in- cludes many varieties, i. 8, § 3 ; iv. 3, § 2 ; [the true kind] has a limit, i. 8, § 14 ; 9, §§ i, 12; popularly confused with coin, ib. 9, §§ 10, 14 ; not so much a concern of household manage- ment as virtue, ib. 13, § i; must be used with both temperance and liberality, ii. 6, § 8 ; vii. 5, § i. Wealth, too highly valued at Sparta and Carthage, ii. 9, §§ 7, 13 ; ir, §§ 8-12; iv. 7, § 4 ; the chief characteristic of oligarchy, ii. II, § 9 ; iii. 8, §7; !▼• 4. §^ 3) 19 ; V. 10, § II ; vi. 2, § 7 ; confers a claim to supe- riority in the state, iii. 9, §§ 4- 6, 15; 12, §§ 8, 9; 13, §§ 1-5; popularly associated with good birth and education, iv. 8, §§4, S ; V. 7, § I. See Riches. \\'ealthy, the, have the external advantages of which the want tempts men to crime, ii. 7, § 10; iv. 8, § 3 ; are apt to be spoiled by the luxury in which they are reared, iv. 1 1 , § 6 ; v. 9, §13; form one of the classes necessary to the state, iv. 14, § 15; vii. S, §§ 7. 9- See Rich. \Miole, the, must be resolved into its parts, i. i, § 3 ; 8, § i ; prior and therefore superior to tlie parts, ib. 2, §§12-14; i"- ^7> § 7 ; the part belongs entirely to the whole, i. 4, § 5 ; every Indi ex 35" 5- whole has a ruling element, ib- 5 J § 3 ; the whole and the part have the same interest, ib. 6, § lo ; the virtue of the parts relative to the virtue of the whole, ib. 13, § 15 ; the happi- ness of the whole dependent on the happiness of the parts, ii. 5, § 27 ; vii. 9, § 7 ; the sophism that ' if the parts are little the whole is little,' v. 8, § 3 ; the care of the part and the care of the whole inseparable, viii. i, §3- Woman, the, has a different virtue to the man, i. 13, §§ 3- 12 ; iii. 4, § 16 ; shares in the deliberative faculty, i. 13, § 7- Women, should be trained with a view to the state, i. 13, § 15 (cp. ii. 9, § 5) ; cannot have the same pursuits as men, ii. 5, §24; said to have been common among certain Libyan tribes, ib. 3, §9; have great influence among warlike races, ib. 9, § 7 ; caused great harm to Sparta by their disorder and licence, ib. §§5-13; possessed two-fifths of the land in Laconia, ib. § 15 ; too proud in oligarchies to be controlled, iv. 15, § 13 ; have often ruined tyrannies by their insolence, v. ir, §23; are allowed great licence in demo- cracies and tyrannies, ib. 11, § 11; vi. 4, §20; commonly cease to bear children after fifty, vii. 16, §§5, 16; should not marry too young, ib. § 6 ; im- part their nature to their ofi^- spring, ib. § 14. Women and children, the com- munity of, proposed by Plato, ii. I, § 3 ; 12, § 12 ; he has not explained whether he would extend it to the dependent classes, ib. 5, §§ 18-24; — objec- tions of Aristotle : (i) unity would not be promoted, ib. 3, §2; (2) there would be a general neglect of the cliildren, ib. § 4 ; (3) the parentage of the children could not be concealed, ib. § 8; (4) expiations would be impos- sible, ib. 4, § I ; (5) the conceal- ment of relationship would lead to unnatural criiues, ib. §§ 1-3, ID; (6) affection would be weakened, ib. §§4-9; (7) the transfer of children to another rank would be found impractic- able, ib. § 10 ; (8) the household would be neglected, ib. 5, § 24. Xerxes, King of Persia, v. 10, § 21. Zaleucus, ii. 12, § 7. Zancle, v. 3, § 12. /w/ 1966 PRINTED IN ENGLAND AT THE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS «. 79,l07,to,f/tJ/^p UnWersUyofCaUfornja ,^Y .j/i